We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
161 \(\Rightarrow\) 9 |
Defining cardinal addition by \(le\)-formulas, Haussler, A. 1983, Fund. Math. |
9 \(\Rightarrow\) 10 | Zermelo's Axiom of Choice, Moore, 1982, 322 |
10 \(\Rightarrow\) 423 | clear |
423 \(\Rightarrow\) 374-n | clear |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
161: | Definability of cardinal addition in terms of \(\le\): There is a first order formula whose only non-logical symbol is \( \le \) (for cardinals) that defines cardinal addition. |
9: | Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite. |
10: | \(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function. |
423: | \(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function. |
374-n: | \(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable. |
Comment: