Listing code1_implications

Hypothesis Conclusion References
52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

L o's-Ryll-Nardzewski-1951,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

L o's-Ryll-Nardzewski-1951, Luxemburg-1970, Luxemburg-1969-1
406

The product of compact Hausdorf spaces is countably compact. Alas [1994].

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Alas-1969,
385

Countable Ultrafilter Theorem:  Every proper filter with a countable base over a set \(S\) (in \({\cal P}(S)\)) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

406

The product of compact Hausdorf spaces is countably compact. Alas [1994].

Alas-1969,
251

The additive groups \(({\Bbb R},+)\) and \(({\Bbb C},+)\) are  isomorphic.

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Ash-1975,
252

The additive groups of \(\Bbb Q\oplus\Bbb R\) and \(\Bbb R\) are isomorphic.

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Ash-1975,
79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

251

The additive groups \(({\Bbb R},+)\) and \(({\Bbb C},+)\) are  isomorphic.

Ash-1975,
79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

252

The additive groups of \(\Bbb Q\oplus\Bbb R\) and \(\Bbb R\) are isomorphic.

Ash-1975,
407

Let \(B\) be a Boolean algebra, \(b\) a non-zero element of \(B\) and \(\{A_i: i\in\omega\}\) a sequence of subsets of \(B\) such that for each \(i\in\omega\), \(A_i\) has a supremum \(a_i\). Then there exists an ultrafilter \(D\) in \(B\) such that \(b\in D\) and, for each \(i\in\omega\), if \(a_i\in D\), then \(D\cap\ A_i\neq\emptyset\).

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

Bacsich-1972b,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

69

Every field has an algebraic closure.  Jech [1973b], p 13.

Banaschewski-1992,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

233

Artin-Schreier theorem: If a field has an algebraic closure it is unique up to isomorphism.

Banaschewski-1992,
303

If \(B\) is a Boolean algebra, \(S\subseteq B\) and \(S\) is closed under \(\land\), then there is a \(\subseteq\)-maximal proper ideal \(I\) of \(B\) such that \(I\cap S= \{0\}\).

50

Sikorski's  Extension Theorem: Every homomorphism of a subalgebra \(B\) of a Boolean algebra \(A\) into a complete Boolean algebra \(B'\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B'\). Sikorski [1964], p. 141.

Bell-1988,
297

Extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces are projective in the category of all compact Hausdorff spaces.

299

Any extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff space is projective in the category of Boolean topological spaces.

Bell-1988,
301

Any continuous surjection between Boolean spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

300

Any continuous surjection between extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

Bell-1988,
302

Any continuous surjection between compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

301

Any continuous surjection between Boolean spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

Bell-1988,
286

Extended Krein-Milman Theorem:  Let K be a quasicompact (sometimes called convex-compact), convex subset of a locally convex topological vector space, then K has an extreme point. H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], p. 177-178.

65

The Krein-Milman Theorem: Let \(K\) be a compact convex set in a locally convex topological vector space \(X\). Then \(K\) has an extreme point. (An extreme point is a point which is not an interior point of any line segment which lies in  \(K\).) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985] p. 177.

Bell-Jellett-1971,
118

Every linearly orderable topological space is normal.  Birkhoff [1967], p 241.

118

Every linearly orderable topological space is normal.  Birkhoff [1967], p 241.

Birkhoff-1967-1
132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

Blass-1977a, Kleinberg-1969,
192

\(EP\) sets: For every set \(A\) there is a projective set \(X\) and a function from \(X\) onto \(A\).

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

Blass-1979,
106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

78

Urysohn's Lemma:  If \(A\) and \(B\) are disjoint closed sets in a normal space \(S\), then there is a continuous \(f:S\rightarrow [0,1]\) which is 1 everywhere in \(A\) and 0 everywhere in \(B\). Urysohn [1925], pp 290-292.

Blass-1979,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

Blass-1979,
188

\(EP\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is a projective Abelian group \(G\) and a homomorphism from \(G\) onto \(A\).

106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

Blass-1979,
106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

Blass-1979,
193

\(EFP\ Ab\): Every Abelian group is a homomorphic image of a free projective Abelian group.

188

\(EP\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is a projective Abelian group \(G\) and a homomorphism from \(G\) onto \(A\).

Blass-1979,
191

\(SVC\): There is a set \(S\) such that for every set \(a\), there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a function from \(S\times\alpha\) onto \(a\).

189

\(EI\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is an injective Abelian group \(G\) and a one to one homomorphism from \(A\) into \(G\).

Blass-1979,
189

\(EI\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is an injective Abelian group \(G\) and a one to one homomorphism from \(A\) into \(G\).

190

There is a non-trivial injective Abelian group.

Blass-1979,
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

Blass-1979, Goldblatt-1985,
191

\(SVC\): There is a set \(S\) such that for every set \(a\), there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a function from \(S\times\alpha\) onto \(a\).

182

There is an aleph whose cofinality is greater than \(\aleph_{0}\).

Blass-1979, Note 59,
66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

Blass-1984a,
110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

Blass-1984a,
26

\(UT(\aleph_{0},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): The union of denumerably many sets each of power \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

26

\(UT(\aleph_{0},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): The union of denumerably many sets each of power \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

Borel-1898,
22

\(UT(2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): If every member of an infinite  set of cardinality \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\), then the union has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

22

\(UT(2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): If every member of an infinite  set of cardinality \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\), then the union has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

Borel-1898, Moore-1982,
24

\(C(\aleph_0,2^{(2^{\aleph_0})})\): Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets each with power \(2^{(2^{\aleph_{0}})}\) has a choice function.

26

\(UT(\aleph_{0},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): The union of denumerably many sets each of power \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

Moore-1982-4 Borel-1898,
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

63

\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
Jech [1973b], p 172 prob 8.5.

Brunner-1982a,
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

Brunner-1982a,
164

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite subset with a Dedekind finite power set.

91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

Brunner-1982a,
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

Brunner-1982a,
78

Urysohn's Lemma:  If \(A\) and \(B\) are disjoint closed sets in a normal space \(S\), then there is a continuous \(f:S\rightarrow [0,1]\) which is 1 everywhere in \(A\) and 0 everywhere in \(B\). Urysohn [1925], pp 290-292.

155
 \(LC\): There are no non-trivial Läuchli continua. (A Läuchli continuum is a strongly connected continuum. Continuum \(\equiv\) compact, connected, Hausdorff space; and strongly connected \(\equiv\) every continuous real valued function is constant.)

Brunner-1983a,
62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

Brunner-1983b,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

154

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many \(T_2\) Spaces: The product of countably many \(T_2\) compact spaces is compact.

Brunner-1983c,
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

154

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many \(T_2\) Spaces: The product of countably many \(T_2\) compact spaces is compact.

Brunner-1983c,
62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

146

\(A(F,A1)\): For every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\), if \(X\) is a continuous finite to one image of an A1 space then \((X,T)\) is  an A1 space. (\((X,T)\) is A1 means if \(U \subseteq  T\) covers \(X\) then \(\exists f : X\rightarrow U\) such that \((\forall x\in X) (x\in f(x)).)\)

Brunner-1983d, Note 26,
149

\(A(F)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space is a continuous, finite to one image of an \(A1\) space.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

Brunner-1983d, Note 26,
147

\(A(D2)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\) can be covered by a well ordered family of discrete sets.

91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

Brunner-1983d, Note 26,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

147

\(A(D2)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\) can be covered by a well ordered family of discrete sets.

Brunner-1983d, Note 26,
17

Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20.

124

Every operator on a Hilbert space with an amorphous base is the direct sum of a finite matrix and  a  scalar operator.  (A set is amorphous if it is not the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Brunner-1984a,
124

Every operator on a Hilbert space with an amorphous base is the direct sum of a finite matrix and  a  scalar operator.  (A set is amorphous if it is not the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

124

Every operator on a Hilbert space with an amorphous base is the direct sum of a finite matrix and  a  scalar operator.  (A set is amorphous if it is not the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Brunner-1984a,
17

Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20.

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

Brunner-1984b,
132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Brunner-1984b,
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Brunner-1984b,
62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Brunner-1984b,
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

Brunner-1984b,
64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

127

An amorphous power of a compact \(T_2\) space, which as a set is well orderable, is well orderable.

Brunner-1984b,
127

An amorphous power of a compact \(T_2\) space, which as a set is well orderable, is well orderable.

127

An amorphous power of a compact \(T_2\) space, which as a set is well orderable, is well orderable.

Brunner-1984b,
125

There does not exist an infinite, compact connected \(p\) space. (A \(p\) space is a \(T_2\) space in which the intersection of any well orderable family of open sets is open.)

125

There does not exist an infinite, compact connected \(p\) space. (A \(p\) space is a \(T_2\) space in which the intersection of any well orderable family of open sets is open.)

Brunner-1984c,
144

Every set is almost well orderable.

125

There does not exist an infinite, compact connected \(p\) space. (A \(p\) space is a \(T_2\) space in which the intersection of any well orderable family of open sets is open.)

Brunner-1984c,
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

145

Compact \(P_0\)-spaces are Dedekind finite. (A \(P_0\)-space is a topological space in which the intersection of a countable collection of open sets is open.)

Brunner-1984c,
129

For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) admits a partition into sets of order type \(\omega^{*} + \omega\). (For every infinite \(A\), there is a set \(\{\langle C_j,<_j \rangle: j\in J\}\) such that \(\{C_j: j\in J\}\) is a partition of \(A\) and for each \(j\in J\), \(<_j\) is an ordering of \(C_j\) of type \(\omega^* + \omega\).)

129

For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) admits a partition into sets of order type \(\omega^{*} + \omega\). (For every infinite \(A\), there is a set \(\{\langle C_j,<_j \rangle: j\in J\}\) such that \(\{C_j: j\in J\}\) is a partition of \(A\) and for each \(j\in J\), \(<_j\) is an ordering of \(C_j\) of type \(\omega^* + \omega\).)

Brunner-1984f,
9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

128

Aczel's Realization Principle: On every infinite set there is a Hausdorff topology with an infinite set of non-isolated points.

Brunner-1984f,
128

Aczel's Realization Principle: On every infinite set there is a Hausdorff topology with an infinite set of non-isolated points.

128

Aczel's Realization Principle: On every infinite set there is a Hausdorff topology with an infinite set of non-isolated points.

Brunner-1984f,
130

\({\cal P}(\Bbb R)\) is well orderable.

130

\({\cal P}(\Bbb R)\) is well orderable.

Brunner-1984f,
114

Every A-bounded \(T_2\) topological space is weakly Loeb. (\(A\)-bounded means amorphous subsets are relatively compact. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

Brunner-1985a,
113

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many Spaces: The product of a countable set of compact spaces is compact.

113

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many Spaces: The product of a countable set of compact spaces is compact.

Brunner-1985a,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

114

Every A-bounded \(T_2\) topological space is weakly Loeb. (\(A\)-bounded means amorphous subsets are relatively compact. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

Brunner-1985a,
114

Every A-bounded \(T_2\) topological space is weakly Loeb. (\(A\)-bounded means amorphous subsets are relatively compact. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

114

Every A-bounded \(T_2\) topological space is weakly Loeb. (\(A\)-bounded means amorphous subsets are relatively compact. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

Brunner-1985a,
115

The product of weakly Loeb \(T_2\) spaces is weakly Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

115

The product of weakly Loeb \(T_2\) spaces is weakly Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

Brunner-1985a,
116

Every compact \(T_2\) space is weakly  Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.

116

Every compact \(T_2\) space is weakly  Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.

Brunner-1985a,
113

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many Spaces: The product of a countable set of compact spaces is compact.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

Kelley-1950, Brunner-1985a,
151

\(UT(WO,\aleph_{0},WO)\) (\(U_{\aleph_{1}}\)): The union of a well ordered set of denumerable sets is well  orderable. (If \(\kappa\) is a well ordered cardinal, see note 27 for \(UT(WO,\kappa,WO)\).)

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Howard-Brunner-1992, Note 27,
152

\(D_{\aleph_{0}}\): Every non-well-orderable set is the union of a pairwise disjoint, well orderable family of denumerable sets.  (See note 27 for \(D_{\kappa}\), \(\kappa\) a well ordered cardinal.)

4

Every infinite set is the union of some disjoint family of denumerable subsets. (Denumerable means \(\cong \aleph_0\).)

Howard-Brunner-1992, Note 27, Note 27, Note 27,
86-alpha

\(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function.

196-alpha

\(\aleph_{\alpha}\) and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) are not both measurable.

Bull-1978,
31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

Cantor-1878,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

141

[14 P(\(n\))] with \(n = 2\):  Let \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\) be a collection of sets such that \(\forall i\in I,\ |A(i)|\le 2\) and suppose \(R\) is a symmetric binary relation on \(\bigcup^{}_{i\in I} A(i)\) such that for all finite \(W\subseteq I\) there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i \in W\}\). Then there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\).

Cowen-1977b,
79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

197

\({\Bbb R}^{2}\) is the union of three sets \(C\) with the property that for all \(x\in C\) there is a straight line \(L\) such that \(L\cap C = \{x\}\).

Davies-1978,
343

A product of non-empty, compact \(T_2\) topological spaces is non-empty.

154

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many \(T_2\) Spaces: The product of countably many \(T_2\) compact spaces is compact.

Hall-Howard-Rubin-De la Cruz-Keremedis-2002,
336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

De la Cruz-Di Prisco-1998a,
378

Restricted Choice for Families of Well Ordered Sets:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that the family of non-empty well orderable subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

De la Cruz-Di Prisco-1998a,
376

Restricted Kinna Wagner Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for every \(z\subseteq Y\), if \(|z| \ge 2\) then \(f(z)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(z\).

377

Restricted Ordering Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that \(Y\) can be linearly ordered.

De la Cruz-Di Prisco-1998a,
12

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\) and every \(n\in\omega\), there is an infinite subset \(B\) of \(A\) such the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco} [1998b]

73

\(\forall n\in\omega\), \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  For every \(n\in\omega\), if \(C\) is an infinite family of \(n\) element sets, then \(C\) has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

De la Cruz-Di Prisco-1998a, De la Cruz-Di Prisco-1998b-1
379

\(PKW(\infty,\infty,\infty)\): For every infinite family \(X\) of sets each of which has at least two elements, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in Y\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(y\).

73

\(\forall n\in\omega\), \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  For every \(n\in\omega\), if \(C\) is an infinite family of \(n\) element sets, then \(C\) has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

De la Cruz-Di Prisco-1998a, De la Cruz-Di Prisco-1998b-1
420

\(UT(\aleph_0\),\(\aleph_0\),cuf): The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is cuf.

34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A,
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

418

DUM(\(\aleph_0\)): The countable disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A,
381

DUM:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

418

DUM(\(\aleph_0\)): The countable disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A,
31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

419

UT(\(\aleph_0\),cuf,cuf): The union of a denumerable set of cuf sets is cuf. (A set is cuf if it is a countable union of finite sets.)

De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A,
418

DUM(\(\aleph_0\)): The countable disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

419

UT(\(\aleph_0\),cuf,cuf): The union of a denumerable set of cuf sets is cuf. (A set is cuf if it is a countable union of finite sets.)

De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A,
419

UT(\(\aleph_0\),cuf,cuf): The union of a denumerable set of cuf sets is cuf. (A set is cuf if it is a countable union of finite sets.)

420

\(UT(\aleph_0\),\(\aleph_0\),cuf): The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is cuf.

De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A,
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

421
  \(UT(\aleph_0,WO,WO)\): The union of a denumerable set of well orderable sets can be well ordered.
De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002B,
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

Dedekind-1888,
9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

Dedekind-1888,
85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

314

For every set \(X\) and every permutation \(\pi\) on \(X\) there are two reflections \(\rho\) and \(\sigma\) on \(X\) such that \(\pi =\rho\circ\sigma\) and for every \(Y\subseteq X\) if \(\pi[Y]=Y\) then \(\rho[Y]=Y\) and \(\sigma[Y]=Y\).  (A reflection is a permutation \(\phi\) such that \(\phi^2\) is the identity.) \ac{Degen} \cite{1988}, \cite{2000}.

Degen-1988, Note 124,
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

411

RCuc (Reflexive Compactness for uniformly convex Banach spaces): The closed unit ball of a uniformly convex Banach space is compact for the weak topology.

Delhomme-Morillon-2000,
144

Every set is almost well orderable.

413

Every infinite set \(S\) is the union of a set, well-ordered by inclusion, of subsets which are non-equipollent to \(S\).  

Ern'e-2001,
144

Every set is almost well orderable.

414

Every \(\cal W\)-frame is a \(\cal D\)-frame.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}

Ern'e-2001,
144

Every set is almost well orderable.

415

Every \(\cal W\)-compactly generated complete lattice is algebraic.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}.

Ern'e-2001,
144

Every set is almost well orderable.

416

Every non-compact topological space \(S\) is the union of a set that is well-ordered by inclusion and consists of open proper subsets of \(S\).

Ern'e-2001,
35

The union of countably many meager subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is meager. (Meager sets are the same as sets of the first category.) Jech [1973b] p 7 prob 1.7.

35

The union of countably many meager subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is meager. (Meager sets are the same as sets of the first category.) Jech [1973b] p 7 prob 1.7.

Levy-Feferman-1963,
25

\(\aleph _{\beta +1}\) is regular for all ordinals \(\beta\).

25

\(\aleph _{\beta +1}\) is regular for all ordinals \(\beta\).

Levy-Feferman-1963, Gitik-1980,
40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

Felgner-1974,
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

408

If \(\{f_i: i\in I\}\) is a family of functions such that for each \(i\in I\), \(f_i\subseteq E\times W\), where \(E\) and \(W\) are non-empty sets, and \(\cal B\) is a filter base on \(I\) such that

  1. For all \(B\in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f_i\) is defined on \(F\), and
  2. For all \(B \in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there exist at most finitely many functions on \(F\) which are restrictions of the functions \(f_i\) with \(i\in I\),  
then there is a function \(f\) with domain \(E\) such that for each finite \(F\subseteq E\) and each \(B\in\cal B\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f|F = f_i|F\).

Felscher-1964,
52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Foreman-Wehrung-1991,
105

There is a  partially ordered set \((A,\le)\) such that for no set \(B\) is \((B,\le)\) (the ordering  on \(B\) is the usual injective cardinal ordering) isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).

105

There is a  partially ordered set \((A,\le)\) such that for no set \(B\) is \((B,\le)\) (the ordering  on \(B\) is the usual injective cardinal ordering) isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).

Forti-Honsell-1985, Jech-1966c,
153

The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact in the weak topology.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Fossy-Morillon-1998,
412

RCh (Reflexive Compactness for Hilbert spaces): The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact for the weak topology.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Fossy-Morillon-1998,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

153

The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact in the weak topology.

Fossy-Morillon-1998,
409

Suppose \((G,\Gamma)\) is a locally finite graph (i.e. \(G\) is a non-empty set and \(\Gamma\) is a function from \(G\) to \(\cal P(G)\) such that for each \(x\in G\), \(\Gamma(x)\) and \(\Gamma^{-1}\{x\}\) are finite), \(K\) is a finite set of integers, and \(T\) is a function mapping subsets of \(K\) into subsets of \(K\). If for each finite subgraph \((A,\Gamma_A)\) there is a function \(\psi\) such that for each \(x\in A\), \(\psi(x)\in T(\psi[\Gamma_A(x)])\), then there is a function \(\phi\) such that for all \(x\in G\), \(\phi(x)\in T(\phi[\Gamma(x)])\).

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

Foster-1964, Note 152,
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

243

Every  principal ideal domain is a unique factorization domain.

Fraleigh-1989-1
108

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\) is not the union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets.

108

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\) is not the union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets.

Gitik-1985,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

298

Every compact Hausdorff space has a Gleason cover.

Bell-1988, Gleason-1958,
387

DPO:  Every infinite set has a non-trivial, dense partial order.  (A partial ordering \(<\) on a set \(X\) is dense if \((\forall x, y\in X)(x \lt y \to (\exists z \in X)(x \lt z \lt y))\) and is non-trivial if \((\exists x,y\in X)(x \lt y)\)).

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Gonzalez-1995a,
30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

387

DPO:  Every infinite set has a non-trivial, dense partial order.  (A partial ordering \(<\) on a set \(X\) is dense if \((\forall x, y\in X)(x \lt y \to (\exists z \in X)(x \lt z \lt y))\) and is non-trivial if \((\exists x,y\in X)(x \lt y)\)).

Gonzalez-1995a,
82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

387

DPO:  Every infinite set has a non-trivial, dense partial order.  (A partial ordering \(<\) on a set \(X\) is dense if \((\forall x, y\in X)(x \lt y \to (\exists z \in X)(x \lt z \lt y))\) and is non-trivial if \((\exists x,y\in X)(x \lt y)\)).

Gonzalez-1995a,
295

DO:  Every infinite set has a dense linear ordering.

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

Gonzalez-1995a,
426

If \((X,\cal T) \) is a first countable topological space and \((\cal B(x))_{x\in X}\) is a family such that for all \(x \in X\), \(\cal B(x)\) is a local base at \(x\), then there is a family \(( \cal V(x))_{x\in X}\) such that for every \(x \in X\), \(\cal V(x)\) is a countable local base at \(x\) and \(\cal V(x) \subseteq \cal B(x)\).

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

Gutierres-2004,
352

A countable product of second countable spaces is second countable.

31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

Gutierres-2004,
426

If \((X,\cal T) \) is a first countable topological space and \((\cal B(x))_{x\in X}\) is a family such that for all \(x \in X\), \(\cal B(x)\) is a local base at \(x\), then there is a family \(( \cal V(x))_{x\in X}\) such that for every \(x \in X\), \(\cal V(x)\) is a countable local base at \(x\) and \(\cal V(x) \subseteq \cal B(x)\).

76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

Gutierres-2004,
424
 Every Lindel\"{o}f metric space is super second countable.  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159. \iput{super second countable}
94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

Gutierres-2004,
16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

352

A countable product of second countable spaces is second countable.

Gutierres-2004,
76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

425
 For every first countable topological space \((X, \Cal T)\) there is a family \((\Cal D(x))_{x \in X}\) such that \(\forall x \in X\), \(D(x)\) countable local base at \(x\).  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159.
Gutierres-2004,
109

Every field \(F\) and every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that each linearly independent set \(A\subseteq V\) can be extended to a basis. H.Rubin/J.~Rubin [1985], pp 119ff.

218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

Rubin-Rubin-1985-3
112

\(MC(\infty,LO)\): For every family \(X\) of non-empty sets each of which can be linearly ordered there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

Rubin-Rubin-1985-2
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

37

Lebesgue measure is countably additive.

Rubin-1985-5
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

130

\({\cal P}(\Bbb R)\) is well orderable.

Rubin-1985-5
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

273

There is a subset of \({\Bbb R}\) which is not Borel.

Rubin-1985-5
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

305

There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Vitali equivalence classes. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).). \ac{Kanovei} \cite{1991}.

Rubin-1985-5
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

309

The Banach-Tarski Paradox: There are three finite partitions \(\{P_1,\ldots\), \(P_n\}\), \(\{Q_1,\ldots,Q_r\}\) and \(\{S_1,\ldots,S_n, T_1,\ldots,T_r\}\) of \(B^3 = \{x\in {\Bbb R}^3 : |x| \le 1\}\) such that \(P_i\) is congruent to \(S_i\) for \(1\le i\le n\) and \(Q_i\) is congruent to \(T_i\) for \(1\le i\le r\).

Rubin-1985-5
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

313

\(\Bbb Z\) (the set of integers under addition) is amenable.  (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

Rubin-1985-5
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

361

In \(\Bbb R\), the union of a denumerable number of analytic sets is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

Rubin-1985-5
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

363

There are exactly \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Borel sets in \(\Bbb R\). G. Moore [1982], p 325.

Rubin-1985-5
161

Definability of cardinal addition in terms of \(\le\): There is a first order formula whose only non-logical symbol is \( \le \) (for cardinals) that defines cardinal addition.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

Haussler-1983,
316

If a linearly ordered set \((A,\le)\) has the fixed point property then \((A,\le)\) is complete. (\((A,\le)\)  has the fixed point property if every function \(f:A\to A\) satisfying \((x\le y \Rightarrow f(x)\le f(y))\) has a fixed point, and (\((A,\le)\) is complete if every subset of \(A\) has a least upper bound.)

77

A linear ordering of a set \(P\) is a well ordering if and only if \(P\) has no infinite descending sequences. Jech [1973b], p 23.

Howard-Hoft-1981,
174-alpha

\(RM1,\aleph_{\alpha }\): The representation theorem for multi-algebras with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations:  Assume \((A,F)\) is  a  multi-algebra  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations (and no other operations). Then  there  is  an  algebra \((B,G)\)  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations and an equivalence relation \(E\) on \(B\) such that \((B/E,G/E)\) and \((A,F)\) are isomorphic multi-algebras.

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

Howard-Hoft-1981,
174-alpha

\(RM1,\aleph_{\alpha }\): The representation theorem for multi-algebras with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations:  Assume \((A,F)\) is  a  multi-algebra  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations (and no other operations). Then  there  is  an  algebra \((B,G)\)  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations and an equivalence relation \(E\) on \(B\) such that \((B/E,G/E)\) and \((A,F)\) are isomorphic multi-algebras.

86-alpha

\(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function.

Howard-Hoft-1981,
87-alpha

\(DC(\aleph_{\alpha})\): Given a relation \(R\) such that for every subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\), there is an \(x\in X\) with \(Y\mathrel R x\) then there is a function \(f:\aleph_{\alpha}\to X\) such that (\(\forall\beta < \aleph_{\alpha}\)) \(\{f(\gamma): \gamma < \beta\}\mathrel R f(\beta)\).

174-alpha

\(RM1,\aleph_{\alpha }\): The representation theorem for multi-algebras with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations:  Assume \((A,F)\) is  a  multi-algebra  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations (and no other operations). Then  there  is  an  algebra \((B,G)\)  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations and an equivalence relation \(E\) on \(B\) such that \((B/E,G/E)\) and \((A,F)\) are isomorphic multi-algebras.

Howard-Hoft-1981,
51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

316

If a linearly ordered set \((A,\le)\) has the fixed point property then \((A,\le)\) is complete. (\((A,\le)\)  has the fixed point property if every function \(f:A\to A\) satisfying \((x\le y \Rightarrow f(x)\le f(y))\) has a fixed point, and (\((A,\le)\) is complete if every subset of \(A\) has a least upper bound.)

Howard-Hoft-1994,
51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

77

A linear ordering of a set \(P\) is a well ordering if and only if \(P\) has no infinite descending sequences. Jech [1973b], p 23.

Howard-Hoft-1994,
185

Every linearly ordered Dedekind finite set is finite.

84

\(E(II,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): \((\forall x)(x\) is \(T\)-finite  if and only if \(\cal P(x)\) is Dedekind finite).

Howard-Hoft-1994,
77

A linear ordering of a set \(P\) is a well ordering if and only if \(P\) has no infinite descending sequences. Jech [1973b], p 23.

185

Every linearly ordered Dedekind finite set is finite.

Howard-Hoft-1994,
123

\(SPI^*\): Uniform weak ultrafilter principle: For each family \(F\) of infinite sets \(\exists f\) such that \(\forall x\in F\), \(f(x)\) is a non-principal ultrafilter on \(x\).

123

\(SPI^*\): Uniform weak ultrafilter principle: For each family \(F\) of infinite sets \(\exists f\) such that \(\forall x\in F\), \(f(x)\) is a non-principal ultrafilter on \(x\).

Halpern-1972,
3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

Howard-Halpern-1974,
3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
4

Every infinite set is the union of some disjoint family of denumerable subsets. (Denumerable means \(\cong \aleph_0\).)

Howard-Brunner-1992, Howard-Halpern-1974, Note 27,
367

There is a Hamel basis for \(\Bbb R\) as a vector space over \(\Bbb Q\).

366

There is a discontinuous function \(f: \Bbb R \to\Bbb R\) such that for all real \(x\) and \(y\), \(f(x+y)=f(x)+f(y)\).

Hamel-1905,
79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

367

There is a Hamel basis for \(\Bbb R\) as a vector space over \(\Bbb Q\).

Hamel-1905,
66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

Hamel-1905,
260

\(Z(TR\&C,P)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
259

\(Z(TR\&C,W)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every well ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
265

\(H(A,TR)\): Every relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

143

\(H(C,TR)\): If \((X,R)\) is a connected relation (\(u\neq v\rightarrow u\mathrel R v\) or \(v\mathrel R u\)) then \(X\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
264

\(H(C,P)\): Every connected relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered set.

202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
89

Antichain Principle:  Every partially ordered set has a maximal antichain. Jech [1973b], p 133.

254

\(Z(D,R,l)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which ramified subsets have least upper bounds, has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
256

\(Z(P,F)\): Every partially ordered set \((X,R)\) in which every forest \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

255

\(Z(D,R)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
258

\(Z(D,L)\): Every directed relation \((X,R)\) in which linearly ordered subsets have upper bounds, has a maximal element.

255

\(Z(D,R)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
262

\(Z(TR,R)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

255

\(Z(D,R)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
261

\(Z(TR,T)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every subset which is a tree has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

256

\(Z(P,F)\): Every partially ordered set \((X,R)\) in which every forest \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
262

\(Z(TR,R)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

257

\(Z(TR,P)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which  every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
256

\(Z(P,F)\): Every partially ordered set \((X,R)\) in which every forest \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

259

\(Z(TR\&C,W)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every well ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

260

\(Z(TR\&C,P)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
255

\(Z(D,R)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

260

\(Z(TR\&C,P)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
257

\(Z(TR,P)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which  every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

260

\(Z(TR\&C,P)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
259

\(Z(TR\&C,W)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every well ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

260

\(Z(TR\&C,P)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
261

\(Z(TR,T)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every subset which is a tree has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

262

\(Z(TR,R)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
143

\(H(C,TR)\): If \((X,R)\) is a connected relation (\(u\neq v\rightarrow u\mathrel R v\) or \(v\mathrel R u\)) then \(X\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

263

\(H(AS\&C,P)\): Every every relation \((X,R)\) which is antisymmetric and connected contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
264

\(H(C,P)\): Every connected relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered set.

263

\(H(AS\&C,P)\): Every every relation \((X,R)\) which is antisymmetric and connected contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
266

\(H(AS,P)\): Every antisymmetric relation contains \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

263

\(H(AS\&C,P)\): Every every relation \((X,R)\) which is antisymmetric and connected contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
265

\(H(A,TR)\): Every relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

266

\(H(AS,P)\): Every antisymmetric relation contains \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

Harper-Rubin-1976,
23

\((\forall \alpha)(UT(\aleph_{\alpha},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): For every ordinal \(\alpha\), if \(A\) and every member of \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\), then \(|\bigcup A| = \aleph _{\alpha }\).

25

\(\aleph _{\beta +1}\) is regular for all ordinals \(\beta\).

Hausdorff-1907,
386

Every B compact (pseudo)metric space is Baire.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Herrlich-Keremedis-1999a,
385

Countable Ultrafilter Theorem:  Every proper filter with a countable base over a set \(S\) (in \({\cal P}(S)\)) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

386

Every B compact (pseudo)metric space is Baire.

Herrlich-Keremedis-1999a,
384

Closed Filter Extendability for \(T_1\) Spaces: Every closed filter in a \(T_1\) topological space can be extended to a maximal closed filter.

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

Herrlich-Steprans-1997,
185

Every linearly ordered Dedekind finite set is finite.

185

Every linearly ordered Dedekind finite set is finite.

Hickman-1979a,
347

Idemmultiple Partition Principle: If \(y\) is idemmultiple (\(2\times y\approx y\)) and \(x\precsim ^* y\), then \(x\precsim y\).

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

Higasikawa-1995,
20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

Higasikawa-1995,
100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

347

Idemmultiple Partition Principle: If \(y\) is idemmultiple (\(2\times y\approx y\)) and \(x\precsim ^* y\), then \(x\precsim y\).

Higasikawa-1995,
79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

Hilbert-1900,
317

Weak Sikorski Theorem:  If \(B\) is a complete, well orderable Boolean algebra and \(f\) is a homomorphism of the Boolean algebra \(A'\) into \(B\) where \(A'\) is a subalgebra of the Boolean algebra \(A\), then \(f\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B\).

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

Howard-1973,
50

Sikorski's  Extension Theorem: Every homomorphism of a subalgebra \(B\) of a Boolean algebra \(A\) into a complete Boolean algebra \(B'\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B'\). Sikorski [1964], p. 141.

317

Weak Sikorski Theorem:  If \(B\) is a complete, well orderable Boolean algebra and \(f\) is a homomorphism of the Boolean algebra \(A'\) into \(B\) where \(A'\) is a subalgebra of the Boolean algebra \(A\), then \(f\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B\).

Howard-1973,
68

Nielsen-Schreier Theorem: Every subgroup of a free group is free.  Jech [1973b], p 12.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

Howard-1985,
29
 If \(|S| = \aleph_{0}\) and \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} A_{x}| = |\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore, G. [1982], p 324.

27

\((\forall \alpha)( UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): The  union of denumerably many sets each of power \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) has power \(\aleph_{\alpha}\). Moore, G. [1982], p 36.

Howard-1994,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

381

DUM:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

Howard-Rubin-Keremedis-Rubin-1998b,
76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

173

\(MPL\): Metric spaces are para-Lindelöf.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Keremedis-2000a,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

232

Every metric space \((X,d)\) has a \(\sigma\)-point finite base.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Keremedis-2000a,
232

Every metric space \((X,d)\) has a \(\sigma\)-point finite base.

173

\(MPL\): Metric spaces are para-Lindelöf.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Keremedis-2000a,
94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

6

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): The union of a denumerable  family  of denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is denumerable.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

35

The union of countably many meager subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is meager. (Meager sets are the same as sets of the first category.) Jech [1973b] p 7 prob 1.7.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
35

The union of countably many meager subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is meager. (Meager sets are the same as sets of the first category.) Jech [1973b] p 7 prob 1.7.

38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
92

\(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

170

\(\aleph_{1}\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

170

\(\aleph_{1}\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
337

\(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered):  If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\).

211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

337

\(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered):  If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\).

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

368

The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

369

If \(\Bbb R\) is partitioned into two sets, at least one of them has cardinality \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
212

\(C(2^{\aleph_{0}},\subseteq{\Bbb R})\): If \(R\) is a relation on \({\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), there is a \(y\in{\Bbb R}\) such that \(x\mathrel R y\), then there is a function \(f: {\Bbb R} \rightarrow{\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), \(x\mathrel R f(x)\).

369

If \(\Bbb R\) is partitioned into two sets, at least one of them has cardinality \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

Howard-Rubin-Stanley-Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001,
292

\(MC(LO,\infty)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

Howard-Rubin-1977,
112

\(MC(\infty,LO)\): For every family \(X\) of non-empty sets each of which can be linearly ordered there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

112

\(MC(\infty,LO)\): For every family \(X\) of non-empty sets each of which can be linearly ordered there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

Howard-Rubin-1977,
88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

276

\(E(V'',III)\): For every set \(A\), \({\cal P}(A)\) is Dedekind finite if and only if \(A = \emptyset\)  or \(2|{\cal P}(A)| > |{\cal P}(A)|\). \ac{Howard/Spi\u siak} \cite{1994}.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

308-p

If \(p\) is a prime and if \(\{G_y: y\in Y\}\) is a set of finite groups, then the weak direct product \(\prod_{y\in Y}G_y\) has a maximal \(p\)-subgroup.

Howard-Yorke-1987,
82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

83

\(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite.

Howard-Yorke-1989,
9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

84

\(E(II,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): \((\forall x)(x\) is \(T\)-finite  if and only if \(\cal P(x)\) is Dedekind finite).

Howard-Yorke-1989,
82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

84

\(E(II,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): \((\forall x)(x\) is \(T\)-finite  if and only if \(\cal P(x)\) is Dedekind finite).

Howard-Yorke-1989,
84

\(E(II,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): \((\forall x)(x\) is \(T\)-finite  if and only if \(\cal P(x)\) is Dedekind finite).

84

\(E(II,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): \((\forall x)(x\) is \(T\)-finite  if and only if \(\cal P(x)\) is Dedekind finite).

Howard-Yorke-1989,
3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
186

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a least upper bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

Rubin-1967,
187

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a greatest lower bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

186

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a least upper bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

Rubin-1967,
40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

Jensen-1967, Jech-1966a,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

89

Antichain Principle:  Every partially ordered set has a maximal antichain. Jech [1973b], p 133.

Jech-1966a,
85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

Jech-1973b-34
68

Nielsen-Schreier Theorem: Every subgroup of a free group is free.  Jech [1973b], p 12.

68

Nielsen-Schreier Theorem: Every subgroup of a free group is free.  Jech [1973b], p 12.

Jech-1973b-4
44

\(DC(\aleph _{1})\):  Given a relation \(R\) such that for every  subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y| < \aleph_{1}\) there is an \(x \in  X\)  with \(Y \mathrel R x\), then there is a function \(f: \aleph_{1} \rightarrow  X\) such that \((\forall\beta < \aleph_{1}) (\{f(\gamma ): \gamma < b \} \mathrel R f(\beta))\).

39

\(C(\aleph_{1},\infty)\): Every set \(A\) of non-empty sets such that \(\vert A\vert = \aleph_{1}\) has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p. 202.

Jech-1973b-26
44

\(DC(\aleph _{1})\):  Given a relation \(R\) such that for every  subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y| < \aleph_{1}\) there is an \(x \in  X\)  with \(Y \mathrel R x\), then there is a function \(f: \aleph_{1} \rightarrow  X\) such that \((\forall\beta < \aleph_{1}) (\{f(\gamma ): \gamma < b \} \mathrel R f(\beta))\).

41

\(W_{\aleph _{1}}\): For every cardinal \(m\), \(m \le \aleph_{1}\) or \(\aleph_{1}\le m \).

Jech-1973b-26
87-alpha

\(DC(\aleph_{\alpha})\): Given a relation \(R\) such that for every subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\), there is an \(x\in X\) with \(Y\mathrel R x\) then there is a function \(f:\aleph_{\alpha}\to X\) such that (\(\forall\beta < \aleph_{\alpha}\)) \(\{f(\gamma): \gamma < \beta\}\mathrel R f(\beta)\).

86-alpha

\(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function.

Levy-1964, Jech-1973b-26 Note 9,
87-alpha

\(DC(\aleph_{\alpha})\): Given a relation \(R\) such that for every subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\), there is an \(x\in X\) with \(Y\mathrel R x\) then there is a function \(f:\aleph_{\alpha}\to X\) such that (\(\forall\beta < \aleph_{\alpha}\)) \(\{f(\gamma): \gamma < \beta\}\mathrel R f(\beta)\).

71-alpha
 

\(W_{\aleph_{\alpha}}\): \((\forall x)(|x|\le\aleph_{\alpha }\) or \(|x|\ge \aleph_{\alpha})\). Jech [1973b], page 119.

Levy-1964, Jech-1973b-26 Note 9,
69

Every field has an algebraic closure.  Jech [1973b], p 13.

69

Every field has an algebraic closure.  Jech [1973b], p 13.

Jech-1973b-5
89

Antichain Principle:  Every partially ordered set has a maximal antichain. Jech [1973b], p 133.

90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

Jech-1973b-45
90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

Jech-1973b-45
90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

Felgner-Jech-1973, Jech-1973b-45
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

Jech-1973b-45 Rubin-Rubin-1985,
89

Antichain Principle:  Every partially ordered set has a maximal antichain. Jech [1973b], p 133.

89

Antichain Principle:  Every partially ordered set has a maximal antichain. Jech [1973b], p 133.

Kurepa-1953, Jech-1973b-45
94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

Jech-1973b-51
94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

Jech-1973b-51
34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

Jech-1973b,
95-F

Existence of Complementary Subspaces over a Field \(F\): If \(F\) is a field, then every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that if \(S\subseteq V\) is a subspace of \(V\), then there is a subspace \(S'\subseteq V\) such that \(S\cap S'= \{0\}\) and \(S\cup S'\) generates \(V\). H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], pp 119ff, and Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.4.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

Bleicher-1964, Jech-1973b-52
97

Cardinal Representatives: For every set \(A\) there is a function \(c\) with domain \({\cal P}(A)\) such that for all \(x, y\in {\cal P}(A)\), (i) \(c(x) = c(y) \leftrightarrow x\approx y\) and (ii) \(c(x)\approx x\).  Jech [1973b] p 154.

97

Cardinal Representatives: For every set \(A\) there is a function \(c\) with domain \({\cal P}(A)\) such that for all \(x, y\in {\cal P}(A)\), (i) \(c(x) = c(y) \leftrightarrow x\approx y\) and (ii) \(c(x)\approx x\).  Jech [1973b] p 154.

Jech-1973b-56
98

The set of all finite subsets of a Dedekind finite set is Dedekind finite. Jech [1973b] p 161 prob 11.5.

98

The set of all finite subsets of a Dedekind finite set is Dedekind finite. Jech [1973b] p 161 prob 11.5.

Jech-1973b-57
7

There is no infinite decreasing sequence of cardinals.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

Tarski-1965, Jech-1973b-58
62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

102

For all Dedekind finite cardinals \(p\) and \(q\), if \(p^{2} = q^{2}\) then \(p = q\). Jech [1973b], p 162 prob 11.12.

Jech-1973b-61
102

For all Dedekind finite cardinals \(p\) and \(q\), if \(p^{2} = q^{2}\) then \(p = q\). Jech [1973b], p 162 prob 11.12.

102

For all Dedekind finite cardinals \(p\) and \(q\), if \(p^{2} = q^{2}\) then \(p = q\). Jech [1973b], p 162 prob 11.12.

Jech-1973b-61
100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

Tarski-1965, Jech-1973b-60
17

Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20.

18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

Blass-1977a, Jech-1973b-62
17

Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20.

17

Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20.

Ramsey-1929, Jech-1973b-62
103

If \((P,<)\) is a linear ordering and \(|P| > \aleph_{1}\) then some initial segment of \(P\) is uncountable. Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.21.

103

If \((P,<)\) is a linear ordering and \(|P| > \aleph_{1}\) then some initial segment of \(P\) is uncountable. Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.21.

Jech-1973b-63
104

There is a regular uncountable aleph. Jech [1966b], p 165 prob 11.26.

104

There is a regular uncountable aleph. Jech [1966b], p 165 prob 11.26.

Jech-1973b-64
63

\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
Jech [1973b], p 172 prob 8.5.

63

\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
Jech [1973b], p 172 prob 8.5.

Jech-1973b-65
74

For every \(A\subseteq\Bbb R\) the following are equivalent:

  1. \(A\) is closed and bounded.
  2. Every sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subseteq A\) has a convergent subsequence with limit in A.
Jech [1973b], p 21.

74

For every \(A\subseteq\Bbb R\) the following are equivalent:

  1. \(A\) is closed and bounded.
  2. Every sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subseteq A\) has a convergent subsequence with limit in A.
Jech [1973b], p 21.

Jech-1973b-6
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

77

A linear ordering of a set \(P\) is a well ordering if and only if \(P\) has no infinite descending sequences. Jech [1973b], p 23.

Jech-1973b-7
77

A linear ordering of a set \(P\) is a well ordering if and only if \(P\) has no infinite descending sequences. Jech [1973b], p 23.

77

A linear ordering of a set \(P\) is a well ordering if and only if \(P\) has no infinite descending sequences. Jech [1973b], p 23.

Jech-1973b-7
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

78

Urysohn's Lemma:  If \(A\) and \(B\) are disjoint closed sets in a normal space \(S\), then there is a continuous \(f:S\rightarrow [0,1]\) which is 1 everywhere in \(A\) and 0 everywhere in \(B\). Urysohn [1925], pp 290-292.

Jech-1973b, Jech-1973b,
83

\(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite.

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Jech-1973b-8
9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

83

\(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite.

Jech-1973b-9
15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

Jech-1973b-10
70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Jech-1973b-2
88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Jech-1973b-2
70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

Jech-1973b-3
88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

Jech-1973b-3
70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

Jech-1973b-18
172

For every infinite set \(S\), if \(S\) is hereditarily countable  (that is, every \(y\in TC(S)\) is countable) then \(|TC(S)|= \aleph_{0}\).

34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

Jech-1982,
184

Existence of a double uniformization: For all \(X\) and \(Y\), for all \(E\subseteq X\times Y\), if there is an infinite cardinal \(\kappa\) satisfying:

  1. \(\forall y_0\in Y\), \(|\{(x,y_0): x\in X\}\cap E| =\kappa\) and
  2. \(\forall x_0\in X\), \(|\{(x_0,y): y\in Y\}\cap E| = \kappa\),
then \(\exists U\subseteq E\) such that for all \((x,y)\in E, \exists !z\in X\) such that \((z,y)\in U\) and \(\exists !z\in Y\) such that \((x,z)\in U\). (\(U\) is called a double uniformization of \(E\).)

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Kaniewski-Rogers-1980,
305

There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Vitali equivalence classes. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).). \ac{Kanovei} \cite{1991}.

306

The set of Vitali equivalence classes is linearly orderable. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow (\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y = q)\).).

Kanovei-1991,
117

If \(\kappa\) is a measurable cardinal, then \(\kappa\) is the \(\kappa\)th inaccessible cardinal.

117

If \(\kappa\) is a measurable cardinal, then \(\kappa\) is the \(\kappa\)th inaccessible cardinal.

Keisler-Tarski-1964,
335-n

Every quotient group of an Abelian group each of whose elements has order  \(\le n\) has a set of representatives.

333

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

Keremedis-1996a,
335-n

Every quotient group of an Abelian group each of whose elements has order  \(\le n\) has a set of representatives.

288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

Keremedis-1996b,
388

Every infinite branching poset (a partially ordered set in which each element has at least two lower bounds) has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

388

Every infinite branching poset (a partially ordered set in which each element has at least two lower bounds) has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

22

\(UT(2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): If every member of an infinite  set of cardinality \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\), then the union has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

139

Using the discrete topology on 2, \(2^{\cal P(\omega)}\) is compact.

139

Using the discrete topology on 2, \(2^{\cal P(\omega)}\) is compact.

389

\(C(\aleph_0,2,\cal P({\Bbb R}))\): Every denumerable family of two element subsets of \(\cal P({\Bbb R})\) has a choice function.  \ac{Keremedis} \cite{1999b}.

352

A countable product of second countable spaces is second countable.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

Keremedis-2000a,
354

A countable product of separable \(T_2\) spaces is separable.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

Keremedis-2000a,
110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

111

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

Keremedis-2000a,
351

A countable product of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

Keremedis-2000a,
353

A countable product of first countable spaces is first countable.

350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

Keremedis-2000a,
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

351

A countable product of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

Keremedis-2000a,
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

352

A countable product of second countable spaces is second countable.

Keremedis-2000a,
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

353

A countable product of first countable spaces is first countable.

Keremedis-2000a,
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

354

A countable product of separable \(T_2\) spaces is separable.

Keremedis-2000a,
154

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many \(T_2\) Spaces: The product of countably many \(T_2\) compact spaces is compact.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

36

Compact T\(_2\) spaces are Loeb. (A space is Loeb if the set of non-empty closed sets has a choice function.)

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001b,
115

The product of weakly Loeb \(T_2\) spaces is weakly Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

118

Every linearly orderable topological space is normal.  Birkhoff [1967], p 241.

Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001b,
36

Compact T\(_2\) spaces are Loeb. (A space is Loeb if the set of non-empty closed sets has a choice function.)

343

A product of non-empty, compact \(T_2\) topological spaces is non-empty.

Tachtsis-Keremedis-2001b,
15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

Kinna-Wagner-1955,
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

17

Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20.

Kleinberg-1969,
9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

17

Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20.

Kleinberg-1969,
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

282

\(\omega\not\to(\omega)^{\omega}\).

Kleinberg-Seiferas-1973, Note 97,
270

\(CT_{\hbox{fin}}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs only in a finite number of formulas.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

Kolany-Wojtylak-1991,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

270

\(CT_{\hbox{fin}}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs only in a finite number of formulas.

Kolany-Wojtylak-1991,
85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

270

\(CT_{\hbox{fin}}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs only in a finite number of formulas.

Kolany-Wojtylak-1991,
270

\(CT_{\hbox{fin}}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs only in a finite number of formulas.

271-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(CT_{n}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs in at most \(n\) formulas.

Kolany-Wojtylak-1991,
88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

268

If \({\cal L}\)  is  a  lattice  isomorphic  to the  lattice  of subalgebras of some unary universal algebra (a unary universal algebra is one with only unary or nullary operations) and \(\alpha \) is an automorphism of \({\cal L}\) of order 2 (that is, \(\alpha ^{2}\)  is  the  identity) then there is a unary algebra \(\frak A\)  and an isomorphism \(\rho \) from \({\cal L}\) onto the lattice of subalgebras of \(\frak A^{2}\) with \[\rho(\alpha(x))=(\rho(x))^{-1} (= \{(s,t) : (t,s)\in\rho(x)\})\] for all \(x\in  {\cal L}\).

Lampe-1974,
268

If \({\cal L}\)  is  a  lattice  isomorphic  to the  lattice  of subalgebras of some unary universal algebra (a unary universal algebra is one with only unary or nullary operations) and \(\alpha \) is an automorphism of \({\cal L}\) of order 2 (that is, \(\alpha ^{2}\)  is  the  identity) then there is a unary algebra \(\frak A\)  and an isomorphism \(\rho \) from \({\cal L}\) onto the lattice of subalgebras of \(\frak A^{2}\) with \[\rho(\alpha(x))=(\rho(x))^{-1} (= \{(s,t) : (t,s)\in\rho(x)\})\] for all \(x\in  {\cal L}\).

269

For every cardinal \(m\), there is a set \(A\) such that \(2^{|A|^2}\ge m\) and there is a choice function on the collection of 2-element subsets of \(A\).

Lampe-1974,
19

A real function is analytically representable if and only if it is in Baire's classification. G.Moore [1982], equation (2.3.1).

19

A real function is analytically representable if and only if it is in Baire's classification. G.Moore [1982], equation (2.3.1).

Lebesgue-1905,
34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

19

A real function is analytically representable if and only if it is in Baire's classification. G.Moore [1982], equation (2.3.1).

Lebesgue-1905,
64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Levy-1958,
82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

Levy-1958,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

Levy-1962,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

144

Every set is almost well orderable.

Levy-1962,
44

\(DC(\aleph _{1})\):  Given a relation \(R\) such that for every  subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y| < \aleph_{1}\) there is an \(x \in  X\)  with \(Y \mathrel R x\), then there is a function \(f: \aleph_{1} \rightarrow  X\) such that \((\forall\beta < \aleph_{1}) (\{f(\gamma ): \gamma < b \} \mathrel R f(\beta))\).

44

\(DC(\aleph _{1})\):  Given a relation \(R\) such that for every  subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y| < \aleph_{1}\) there is an \(x \in  X\)  with \(Y \mathrel R x\), then there is a function \(f: \aleph_{1} \rightarrow  X\) such that \((\forall\beta < \aleph_{1}) (\{f(\gamma ): \gamma < b \} \mathrel R f(\beta))\).

Levy-1964,
86-alpha

\(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function.

86-alpha

\(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function.

Levy-1964,
87-alpha

\(DC(\aleph_{\alpha})\): Given a relation \(R\) such that for every subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\), there is an \(x\in X\) with \(Y\mathrel R x\) then there is a function \(f:\aleph_{\alpha}\to X\) such that (\(\forall\beta < \aleph_{\alpha}\)) \(\{f(\gamma): \gamma < \beta\}\mathrel R f(\beta)\).

87-alpha

\(DC(\aleph_{\alpha})\): Given a relation \(R\) such that for every subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\), there is an \(x\in X\) with \(Y\mathrel R x\) then there is a function \(f:\aleph_{\alpha}\to X\) such that (\(\forall\beta < \aleph_{\alpha}\)) \(\{f(\gamma): \gamma < \beta\}\mathrel R f(\beta)\).

Levy-1964,
44

\(DC(\aleph _{1})\):  Given a relation \(R\) such that for every  subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y| < \aleph_{1}\) there is an \(x \in  X\)  with \(Y \mathrel R x\), then there is a function \(f: \aleph_{1} \rightarrow  X\) such that \((\forall\beta < \aleph_{1}) (\{f(\gamma ): \gamma < b \} \mathrel R f(\beta))\).

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

Levy-1964, Jech-1973b-26
100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

369

If \(\Bbb R\) is partitioned into two sets, at least one of them has cardinality \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

Lindenbaum-Tarski-1926,
100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

Lindenbaum-Tarski-1926,
100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Lindenbaum-Tarski-1926, Moore-1982,
245

There is a function \(f :\omega_1\rightarrow \omega^{\omega}_1\) such that for every \(\alpha\), \(0 < \alpha < \omega_1\), \(f(\alpha )\) is a function from \(\omega\) onto \(\alpha\).

34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

Litman-1976,
245

There is a function \(f :\omega_1\rightarrow \omega^{\omega}_1\) such that for every \(\alpha\), \(0 < \alpha < \omega_1\), \(f(\alpha )\) is a function from \(\omega\) onto \(\alpha\).

246

The monadic theory theory \(MT(\omega_1,<)\) of \(\omega_1\) is recursive.  \ac{Litman} \cite{1976} and note 85.

Litman-1976,
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

107
 

M. Hall's Theorem: Let \(\{S(\alpha): \alpha\in A\}\) be a collection of finite subsets (of a set \(X\)) then if

(*) for each finite \(F \subseteq  A\) there is an injective choice function on \(F\)
then there is an injective choice function on \(A\). (That is, a 1-1 function \(f\) such that \((\forall\alpha\in A)(f(\alpha)\in S(\alpha))\).) (According to a theorem of P. Hall (\(*\)) is equivalent to \(\left |\bigcup_{\alpha\in F} S(\alpha)\right|\ge |F|\). P. Hall's theorem does not require the axiom of choice.)

Hall-1948,
59-le

If \((A,\le)\) is a partial ordering that is not a well ordering, then there is no set \(B\) such that \((B,\le)\) (the usual injective cardinal ordering on \(B\)) is isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).
Mathias [1979], p 120.

59-le

If \((A,\le)\) is a partial ordering that is not a well ordering, then there is no set \(B\) such that \((B,\le)\) (the usual injective cardinal ordering on \(B\)) is isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).
Mathias [1979], p 120.

Mathias-1979,
50

Sikorski's  Extension Theorem: Every homomorphism of a subalgebra \(B\) of a Boolean algebra \(A\) into a complete Boolean algebra \(B'\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B'\). Sikorski [1964], p. 141.

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

Mathias-1979,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

49

Order Extension Principle: Every partial ordering can be extended to a linear ordering.  Tarski [1924], p 78.

Mathias-1979,
55

For all infinite cardinals \(m\) and \(n\), if \(m\cdot n = m + n\) then, \(m \le  n\) or \(n \le m\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

55

For all infinite cardinals \(m\) and \(n\), if \(m\cdot n = m + n\) then, \(m \le  n\) or \(n \le m\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

Mathias-1979,
56

\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{0}})\neq\aleph_{\omega}\). (\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{0}})\) is Hartogs' aleph, the least \(\aleph\) not \(\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).)
Mathias [1979], p 125.

56

\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{0}})\neq\aleph_{\omega}\). (\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{0}})\) is Hartogs' aleph, the least \(\aleph\) not \(\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).)
Mathias [1979], p 125.

Mathias-1979,
57

If \(x\) and \(y\) are Dedekind finite sets then either \(|x|\le |y|\) or \(|y|\le |x|\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

57

If \(x\) and \(y\) are Dedekind finite sets then either \(|x|\le |y|\) or \(|y|\le |x|\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

Mathias-1979,
58

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\neq\aleph_{\alpha +1}\). (\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}})\) is Hartogs' aleph, the least \(\aleph\) not \(\le 2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\).)
Mathias [1979], p 126.

58

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\neq\aleph_{\alpha +1}\). (\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}})\) is Hartogs' aleph, the least \(\aleph\) not \(\le 2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\).)
Mathias [1979], p 126.

Mathias-1979,
53

For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(m^2\le 2^m\).  Mathias [1979], prob 1336.

53

For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(m^2\le 2^m\).  Mathias [1979], prob 1336.

Mathias-1979,
54

For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(m\) adj \(2^{m}\) implies \(m\) is an aleph.  
Note that \(m\) adj \(n\) iff \(m < n\) and \(\neg (\exists p) (m < p < n).\)
Mathias [1979] prob 1337, thm 1338 and prob 1339.

54

For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(m\) adj \(2^{m}\) implies \(m\) is an aleph.  
Note that \(m\) adj \(n\) iff \(m < n\) and \(\neg (\exists p) (m < p < n).\)
Mathias [1979] prob 1337, thm 1338 and prob 1339.

Mathias-1979,
107
 

M. Hall's Theorem: Let \(\{S(\alpha): \alpha\in A\}\) be a collection of finite subsets (of a set \(X\)) then if

(*) for each finite \(F \subseteq  A\) there is an injective choice function on \(F\)
then there is an injective choice function on \(A\). (That is, a 1-1 function \(f\) such that \((\forall\alpha\in A)(f(\alpha)\in S(\alpha))\).) (According to a theorem of P. Hall (\(*\)) is equivalent to \(\left |\bigcup_{\alpha\in F} S(\alpha)\right|\ge |F|\). P. Hall's theorem does not require the axiom of choice.)

96

Löwig's Theorem:If \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are both bases for the vector space \(V\) then \(|B_{1}| = |B_{2}|\).

Mirsky-1971,
15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

Monro-1972,
345

Rasiowa-Sikorski Axiom:  If \((B,\land,\lor)\) is a Boolean algebra, \(a\) is a non-zero element of \(B\), and \(\{X_n: n\in\omega\}\) is a denumerable set of subsets of \(B\) then there is a maximal filter \(F\) of \(B\) such that \(a\in F\) and for each \(n\in\omega\), if \(X_n\subseteq F\) and \(\bigwedge X_n\) exists then \(\bigwedge X_n \in F\).

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

Morillon-1988,
345

Rasiowa-Sikorski Axiom:  If \((B,\land,\lor)\) is a Boolean algebra, \(a\) is a non-zero element of \(B\), and \(\{X_n: n\in\omega\}\) is a denumerable set of subsets of \(B\) then there is a maximal filter \(F\) of \(B\) such that \(a\in F\) and for each \(n\in\omega\), if \(X_n\subseteq F\) and \(\bigwedge X_n\) exists then \(\bigwedge X_n \in F\).

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

Morillon-1988,
123

\(SPI^*\): Uniform weak ultrafilter principle: For each family \(F\) of infinite sets \(\exists f\) such that \(\forall x\in F\), \(f(x)\) is a non-principal ultrafilter on \(x\).

331

If \((X_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of compact non-empty topological spaces then there is a family \((F_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(F_i\) is an irreducible closed subset of \(X_i\).

Morillon-1988,
331

If \((X_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of compact non-empty topological spaces then there is a family \((F_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(F_i\) is an irreducible closed subset of \(X_i\).

332
 

A product of non-empty compact sober topological spaces is non-empty.

Morillon-1988,
332
 

A product of non-empty compact sober topological spaces is non-empty.

343

A product of non-empty, compact \(T_2\) topological spaces is non-empty.

Morillon-1988,
123

\(SPI^*\): Uniform weak ultrafilter principle: For each family \(F\) of infinite sets \(\exists f\) such that \(\forall x\in F\), \(f(x)\) is a non-principal ultrafilter on \(x\).

344

If \((E_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of non-empty sets, then there is a family \((U_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(U_i\) is an ultrafilter on \(E_i\).

Morillon-1988,
286

Extended Krein-Milman Theorem:  Let K be a quasicompact (sometimes called convex-compact), convex subset of a locally convex topological vector space, then K has an extreme point. H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], p. 177-178.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

Morillon-1991b-1
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

371

There is an infinite, compact, Hausdorff, extremally disconnected topological space.  Morillon [1993].

Morillon-1993-1
79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

371

There is an infinite, compact, Hausdorff, extremally disconnected topological space.  Morillon [1993].

Morillon-1993-1
51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

208

For all ordinals \(\alpha\), \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\le 2^{\aleph_\alpha}\).

Morris-1969,
51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

25

\(\aleph _{\beta +1}\) is regular for all ordinals \(\beta\).

Morris-1969,
51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

294

Every linearly ordered \(W\)-set is well orderable.

Morris-1969,
45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

Mostowski-1945, Truss-1973a,
46-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,K)\): For every \(n\in K\), every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

46-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,K)\): For every \(n\in K\), every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

Mostowski-1945, Truss-1973a,
47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

Mostowski-1945, Truss-1973a,
48-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,K)\): For every \(n\in K,\) \(C(WO,n)\).

48-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,K)\): For every \(n\in K,\) \(C(WO,n)\).

Truss-1973a, Mostowski-1945,
80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

Mostowski-1948,
52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

309

The Banach-Tarski Paradox: There are three finite partitions \(\{P_1,\ldots\), \(P_n\}\), \(\{Q_1,\ldots,Q_r\}\) and \(\{S_1,\ldots,S_n, T_1,\ldots,T_r\}\) of \(B^3 = \{x\in {\Bbb R}^3 : |x| \le 1\}\) such that \(P_i\) is congruent to \(S_i\) for \(1\le i\le n\) and \(Q_i\) is congruent to \(T_i\) for \(1\le i\le r\).

Pawlikowski-1991,
101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

Pelc-1978,
101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

Pelc-1978,
101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

205

For all cardinals \(m\) and \(n\), if \(m\le^* n\) and \(\neg (n\le^* m)\) then there is a cardinal \(k \le n\) such that \(m\le^* k\).

Pelc-1978,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

Pincus-1972b,
222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

Pincus-1972c,
70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

Pincus-1972c,
123

\(SPI^*\): Uniform weak ultrafilter principle: For each family \(F\) of infinite sets \(\exists f\) such that \(\forall x\in F\), \(f(x)\) is a non-principal ultrafilter on \(x\).

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

Pincus-1976,
15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

295

DO:  Every infinite set has a dense linear ordering.

Pincus-1997,
15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

296

Part-\(\infty\): Every infinite set is the disjoint union of infinitely many infinite sets.

Pincus-1997,
99

Rado's Selection Lemma: Let \(\{K(\lambda): \lambda \in\Lambda\}\) be a family  of finite subsets (of \(X\)) and suppose for each finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a function \(\gamma(S): S \rightarrow X\) such that \((\forall\lambda\in S)(\gamma(S)(\lambda)\in K(\lambda))\).  Then there is an \(f: \Lambda\rightarrow X\) such that for every finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a finite \(T\) such that \(S\subseteq T\subseteq\Lambda\) and such that \(f\) and \(\gamma (T)\) agree on S.

99

Rado's Selection Lemma: Let \(\{K(\lambda): \lambda \in\Lambda\}\) be a family  of finite subsets (of \(X\)) and suppose for each finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a function \(\gamma(S): S \rightarrow X\) such that \((\forall\lambda\in S)(\gamma(S)(\lambda)\in K(\lambda))\).  Then there is an \(f: \Lambda\rightarrow X\) such that for every finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a finite \(T\) such that \(S\subseteq T\subseteq\Lambda\) and such that \(f\) and \(\gamma (T)\) agree on S.

Rado-1949,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

99

Rado's Selection Lemma: Let \(\{K(\lambda): \lambda \in\Lambda\}\) be a family  of finite subsets (of \(X\)) and suppose for each finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a function \(\gamma(S): S \rightarrow X\) such that \((\forall\lambda\in S)(\gamma(S)(\lambda)\in K(\lambda))\).  Then there is an \(f: \Lambda\rightarrow X\) such that for every finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a finite \(T\) such that \(S\subseteq T\subseteq\Lambda\) and such that \(f\) and \(\gamma (T)\) agree on S.

Rav-1977,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

123

\(SPI^*\): Uniform weak ultrafilter principle: For each family \(F\) of infinite sets \(\exists f\) such that \(\forall x\in F\), \(f(x)\) is a non-principal ultrafilter on \(x\).

Rav-1977,
99

Rado's Selection Lemma: Let \(\{K(\lambda): \lambda \in\Lambda\}\) be a family  of finite subsets (of \(X\)) and suppose for each finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a function \(\gamma(S): S \rightarrow X\) such that \((\forall\lambda\in S)(\gamma(S)(\lambda)\in K(\lambda))\).  Then there is an \(f: \Lambda\rightarrow X\) such that for every finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a finite \(T\) such that \(S\subseteq T\subseteq\Lambda\) and such that \(f\) and \(\gamma (T)\) agree on S.

225

Every proper filter on \(\omega\) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

Rav-1977,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

226

Let \(R\) be a commutative ring with identity, \(B\) a proper subring containing 1 and \(q\) a prime ideal in \(B\). Then there is a subring \(A\) of \(R\) and a prime ideal \(p\) in \(A\) such that

  1. \(B\subseteq A\)
  2. \(q = B\cap p\)
  3. \(R - p\) is multiplicatively closed and
  4. if \(A\neq R\),
then \(R - A\) is multiplicatively closed.

Rav-1977,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

227

For all groups \(G\), if every finite subgroup of \(G\) can be fully ordered then \(G\) can be fully ordered.

Rav-1977,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

228

Every torsion free Abelian group can be fully ordered.

Rav-1977,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

229

If \((G,\circ,\le)\) is a partially ordered group, then \(\le\) can be extended to a linear order on \(G\) if and only if for every finite set \(\{a_{1},\ldots, a_{n}\}\subseteq G\), with \(a_{i}\neq\) the identity for \(i = 1\) to \(n\), the signs \(\epsilon_{1}, \ldots,\epsilon_{n}\) (\(\epsilon_{i} = \pm 1\)) can be chosen so that \(P\cap S(a^{\epsilon_{1}}_{1},\ldots,a^{\epsilon_{n}}_{n})=\emptyset\) (where \(S(b_{1},\ldots,b_{n})\) is the normal sub-semi-group of \(G\) generated by \(b_{1},\ldots, b_{n}\) and \(P = \{g\in G: e\le g\}\) where \(e\) is the identity of \(G\).)

Rav-1977,
5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

Sageev-1975,
99

Rado's Selection Lemma: Let \(\{K(\lambda): \lambda \in\Lambda\}\) be a family  of finite subsets (of \(X\)) and suppose for each finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a function \(\gamma(S): S \rightarrow X\) such that \((\forall\lambda\in S)(\gamma(S)(\lambda)\in K(\lambda))\).  Then there is an \(f: \Lambda\rightarrow X\) such that for every finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a finite \(T\) such that \(S\subseteq T\subseteq\Lambda\) and such that \(f\) and \(\gamma (T)\) agree on S.

70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

Schechter-1996a,
7

There is no infinite decreasing sequence of cardinals.

7

There is no infinite decreasing sequence of cardinals.

Schoenflies-1908,
30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

Schroder-1898,
201

Linking Axiom for Boolean Algebras: Every Boolean algebra has a maximal linked system. (\(L\subseteq B\) is linked if \(a\wedge b\neq 0\) for all \(a\) and \(b \in L\).)

88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

Schrijver-1978,
49

Order Extension Principle: Every partial ordering can be extended to a linear ordering.  Tarski [1924], p 78.

201

Linking Axiom for Boolean Algebras: Every Boolean algebra has a maximal linked system. (\(L\subseteq B\) is linked if \(a\wedge b\neq 0\) for all \(a\) and \(b \in L\).)

Schrijver-1978,
37

Lebesgue measure is countably additive.

37

Lebesgue measure is countably additive.

Sierpi'nski-1916,
368

The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Sierpi'nski-1917,
306

The set of Vitali equivalence classes is linearly orderable. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow (\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y = q)\).).

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Sierpi'nski-1918,
6

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): The union of a denumerable  family  of denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is denumerable.

5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

Sierpi'nski-1918,
16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

6

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): The union of a denumerable  family  of denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is denumerable.

Sierpi'nski-1918,
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

Sierpi'nski-1918,
16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

Sierpi'nski-1918,
31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

Sierpi'nski-1918,
32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

Sierpi'nski-1918,
37

Lebesgue measure is countably additive.

38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

Sierpi'nski-1918,
51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

Sierpi'nski-1918,
39

\(C(\aleph_{1},\infty)\): Every set \(A\) of non-empty sets such that \(\vert A\vert = \aleph_{1}\) has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p. 202.

39

\(C(\aleph_{1},\infty)\): Every set \(A\) of non-empty sets such that \(\vert A\vert = \aleph_{1}\) has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p. 202.

Sierpi'nski-1918, Moore-1982,
101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Sierpi'nski-1918, Sierpi'nski-1947, Moore-1982,
101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

Sierpi'nski-1947,
83

\(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite.

83

\(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite.

Tarski-1924,
49

Order Extension Principle: Every partial ordering can be extended to a linear ordering.  Tarski [1924], p 78.

49

Order Extension Principle: Every partial ordering can be extended to a linear ordering.  Tarski [1924], p 78.

Tarski-1924,
368

The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

170

\(\aleph_{1}\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

Tarski-1939,
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

Tarski-1948, Levy-1964,
2

Existence of successor cardinals: For every cardinal \(m\) there is a cardinal \(n\) such that \(m < n\) and \((\forall p < n)(p \le m)\).

2

Existence of successor cardinals: For every cardinal \(m\) there is a cardinal \(n\) such that \(m < n\) and \((\forall p < n)(p \le m)\).

Tarski-1954a,
3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
Tarski-1954a,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

72

Artin-Schreier Theorem:  Every field in which \(-1\) is not the sum of squares can be ordered. (The ordering, \(\le \), must satisfy (a) \(a\le b\rightarrow a + c\le b + c\) for all \(c\) and (b) \(c\ge 0\) and \(a\le b\rightarrow a\cdot c\le b\cdot c\).)

Tarski-1954b,
72

Artin-Schreier Theorem:  Every field in which \(-1\) is not the sum of squares can be ordered. (The ordering, \(\le \), must satisfy (a) \(a\le b\rightarrow a + c\le b + c\) for all \(c\) and (b) \(c\ge 0\) and \(a\le b\rightarrow a\cdot c\le b\cdot c\).)

72

Artin-Schreier Theorem:  Every field in which \(-1\) is not the sum of squares can be ordered. (The ordering, \(\le \), must satisfy (a) \(a\le b\rightarrow a + c\le b + c\) for all \(c\) and (b) \(c\ge 0\) and \(a\le b\rightarrow a\cdot c\le b\cdot c\).)

Tarski-1954b,
33-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,n)\):  Every linearly ordered set of \(n\) element sets has  a choice function.

33-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,n)\):  Every linearly ordered set of \(n\) element sets has  a choice function.

Truss-1973a,
120-K

If \(K\subseteq\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,K)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty sets each of whose cardinality is in \(K\) has a choice function.

120-K

If \(K\subseteq\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,K)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty sets each of whose cardinality is in \(K\) has a choice function.

Truss-1973a,
121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Truss-1973a,
122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Truss-1973a,
2

Existence of successor cardinals: For every cardinal \(m\) there is a cardinal \(n\) such that \(m < n\) and \((\forall p < n)(p \le m)\).

3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
Truss-1973c,
62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

283

Cardinality of well ordered subsets:  For all \(n\in\omega\) and for all infinite \(x\), \(|x^n| < |s(x)|\) where \(s(x)\) is the set of all well orderable subsets of \(x\).

Truss-1973d,
45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Truss-1974a,
57

If \(x\) and \(y\) are Dedekind finite sets then either \(|x|\le |y|\) or \(|y|\le |x|\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Truss-1974a,
88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Truss-1974a,
79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

272

There is an \(X\subseteq{\Bbb R}\) such that neither \(X\) nor \(\Bbb R - X\) has a perfect subset.

Truss-1974b,
138-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega\).  If \(f\) is a partial map from \(k\times Y\)  onto \(k\times X\) (that is, the domain is a subset of \(k\times Y\)), then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i}\)  and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i}\) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times Y_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup^{}_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times X_{i})\).

136-k

Surjective Cardinal Cancellation (depends on \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\)): For all cardinals \(x\) and \(y\), \(kx\le^* ky\) implies \(x\le^* y\).

Truss-1984,
139

Using the discrete topology on 2, \(2^{\cal P(\omega)}\) is compact.

137-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\). If \(f\) is a 1-1 map from \(k\times X\) into \(k\times Y\) then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i} \) and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i} \) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  X_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  Y_{i})\).

Truss-1984,
60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

Tsukada-1977,
78

Urysohn's Lemma:  If \(A\) and \(B\) are disjoint closed sets in a normal space \(S\), then there is a continuous \(f:S\rightarrow [0,1]\) which is 1 everywhere in \(A\) and 0 everywhere in \(B\). Urysohn [1925], pp 290-292.

78

Urysohn's Lemma:  If \(A\) and \(B\) are disjoint closed sets in a normal space \(S\), then there is a continuous \(f:S\rightarrow [0,1]\) which is 1 everywhere in \(A\) and 0 everywhere in \(B\). Urysohn [1925], pp 290-292.

Urysohn-1925,
310

The Measure Extension Theorem: Suppose that \(\cal A_0\) is a subring (that is, \(a,b \in \cal A_0  \to a\vee b \in \cal A_0\) and \(a-b \in \cal A_0\)) of a Boolean algebra \(\cal A\) and \(\mu\) is a measure on \(\cal A_0\) (that is, \(\mu:\cal A \to [0,\infty]\), \(\mu(a\vee b) =\mu(a)+\mu(b)\) for \(a\land b = 0\), and \(\mu(0) = 0\).) then there is a measure on \(\cal A\) that extends \(\mu\).

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

Wagon-1985,
311

Abelian groups are amenable. (\(G\) is amenable if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G)=1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

Wagon-1985,
313

\(\Bbb Z\) (the set of integers under addition) is amenable.  (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

Wagon-1985,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

311

Abelian groups are amenable. (\(G\) is amenable if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G)=1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

Wagon-1985,
4

Every infinite set is the union of some disjoint family of denumerable subsets. (Denumerable means \(\cong \aleph_0\).)

4

Every infinite set is the union of some disjoint family of denumerable subsets. (Denumerable means \(\cong \aleph_0\).)

Whitehead-1902,
62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

285

Let \(E\) be a set and \(f: E\to E\), then \(f\) has a fixed point if and only if \(E\) is not the union of three mutually disjoint sets \(E_1\), \(E_2\) and \(E_3\) such that \(E_i \cap f(E_i) = \emptyset\) for \(i=1, 2, 3\).

Wi'sniewski-1973,
326

2-SAT:  Restricted Compactness Theorem for Propositional Logic III:   If \(\Sigma\) is a set of formulas in a propositional language such that every finite subset of \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable and if every formula in \(\Sigma\) is a disjunction of at most two literals, then \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable. (A literal is a propositional variable or its negation.) Wojtylak [1999] (listed as Wojtylak [1995])

88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

Wojtylak-1999-1
49

Order Extension Principle: Every partial ordering can be extended to a linear ordering.  Tarski [1924], p 78.

326

2-SAT:  Restricted Compactness Theorem for Propositional Logic III:   If \(\Sigma\) is a set of formulas in a propositional language such that every finite subset of \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable and if every formula in \(\Sigma\) is a disjunction of at most two literals, then \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable. (A literal is a propositional variable or its negation.) Wojtylak [1999] (listed as Wojtylak [1995])

Wojtylak-1999-1
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

279

The Closed Graph Theorem for operations between Fréchet Spaces: Suppose \(X\) and \(Y\) are Fréchet spaces, \(T:X\to Y\) is linear and \(G=\{(x,Tx): x \in X \}\) is closed in \(X\times Y\). Then \(T\) is continuous. Rudin [1991] p. 51.

Wright-1973,
61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

11

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) has an infinite subset \(B\) such that for every \(n\in\omega\), \(n>0\), the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

378

Restricted Choice for Families of Well Ordered Sets:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that the family of non-empty well orderable subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

11

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) has an infinite subset \(B\) such that for every \(n\in\omega\), \(n>0\), the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

11

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) has an infinite subset \(B\) such that for every \(n\in\omega\), \(n>0\), the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

12

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\) and every \(n\in\omega\), there is an infinite subset \(B\) of \(A\) such the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco} [1998b]

325

Ramsey's Theorem II: \(\forall n,m\in\omega\), if A is an infinite set and the family of all \(m\) element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into \(n\) sets \(S_{j}, 1\le j\le n\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all \(m\) element subsets of \(B\) belong to the same \(S_{j}\). (Also, see Form 17.)

17

Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20.

359

If \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| \le |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| \le |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\).

20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

150

\(PC(\infty,\aleph_0,\infty)\): Every infinite set of denumerable sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

363

There are exactly \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Borel sets in \(\Bbb R\). G. Moore [1982], p 325.

38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

42

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem: If a countable family of first order  sentences is satisfiable in a set \(M\) then it is satisfiable in a countable subset of \(M\). (See Moore, G. [1982], p. 251 for references.

218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

343

A product of non-empty, compact \(T_2\) topological spaces is non-empty.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

344

If \((E_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of non-empty sets, then there is a family \((U_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(U_i\) is an ultrafilter on \(E_i\).

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

408

If \(\{f_i: i\in I\}\) is a family of functions such that for each \(i\in I\), \(f_i\subseteq E\times W\), where \(E\) and \(W\) are non-empty sets, and \(\cal B\) is a filter base on \(I\) such that

  1. For all \(B\in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f_i\) is defined on \(F\), and
  2. For all \(B \in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there exist at most finitely many functions on \(F\) which are restrictions of the functions \(f_i\) with \(i\in I\),  
then there is a function \(f\) with domain \(E\) such that for each finite \(F\subseteq E\) and each \(B\in\cal B\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f|F = f_i|F\).

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

296

Part-\(\infty\): Every infinite set is the disjoint union of infinitely many infinite sets.

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

333

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

334

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\hbox{ even})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is even.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

430-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) \(AL21\)\((p)\): Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that for every subspace \(S\) of \(V\), there is a subspace \(S'\) of \(V\) such that \(S \cap S' = \{ 0 \}\) and \(S \cup S'\) generates \(V\) in other words such that \(V = S \oplus S'\).   Rubin, H./Rubin, J [1985], p.119, AL21.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

73

\(\forall n\in\omega\), \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  For every \(n\in\omega\), if \(C\) is an infinite family of \(n\) element sets, then \(C\) has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

405

Every infinite set can be partitioned into sets each of which is countable and has at least two elements.

75

If a set has at least two elements, then it can be partitioned into well orderable subsets, each of which has at least two elements.

214

\(Z(\omega)\): For every family \(A\) of infinite sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in A\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty subset of \(y\) and \(|f(y)|=\aleph_{0}\).

76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

375

Tietze-Urysohn Extension Theorem: If \((X,T)\) is a normal topological space, \(A\) is closed in \(X\), and \(f: A\to [0,1]\) is continuous, then there exists a continuous function \(g: X\to [0,1]\) which extends \(f\).

78

Urysohn's Lemma:  If \(A\) and \(B\) are disjoint closed sets in a normal space \(S\), then there is a continuous \(f:S\rightarrow [0,1]\) which is 1 everywhere in \(A\) and 0 everywhere in \(B\). Urysohn [1925], pp 290-292.

111

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

358

\(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

92

\(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

130

\({\cal P}(\Bbb R)\) is well orderable.

92

\(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

309

The Banach-Tarski Paradox: There are three finite partitions \(\{P_1,\ldots\), \(P_n\}\), \(\{Q_1,\ldots,Q_r\}\) and \(\{S_1,\ldots,S_n, T_1,\ldots,T_r\}\) of \(B^3 = \{x\in {\Bbb R}^3 : |x| \le 1\}\) such that \(P_i\) is congruent to \(S_i\) for \(1\le i\le n\) and \(Q_i\) is congruent to \(T_i\) for \(1\le i\le r\).

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

92

\(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

239

AL20(\(\mathbb Q\)):  Every vector \(V\) space over \(\mathbb Q\) has the property that every linearly independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis. Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p.119, AL20.

110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

111

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

422-n

\(UT(WO,n,WO)\), \(n\in \omega-\{0,1\}\): The union of a well ordered set of \(n\) element sets can be well ordered.

111

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

391

\(C(\infty,LO)\): Every set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

112

\(MC(\infty,LO)\): For every family \(X\) of non-empty sets each of which can be linearly ordered there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

36

Compact T\(_2\) spaces are Loeb. (A space is Loeb if the set of non-empty closed sets has a choice function.)

116

Every compact \(T_2\) space is weakly  Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

116

Every compact \(T_2\) space is weakly  Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.

393

\(C(LO,WO)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty well orderable sets has a choice function.

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

328

\(MC(WO,\infty)\): For  every well ordered set \(X\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that and for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\). (See Form 67.)

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

131

\(MC_\omega(\aleph_0,\infty)\): For every denumerable family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

150

\(PC(\infty,\aleph_0,\infty)\): Every infinite set of denumerable sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

380

\(PC(\infty,WO,\infty)\):  For every infinite family of non-empty well orderable sets, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) which has a choice function.

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

150

\(PC(\infty,\aleph_0,\infty)\): Every infinite set of denumerable sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

150

\(PC(\infty,\aleph_0,\infty)\): Every infinite set of denumerable sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

393

\(C(LO,WO)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty well orderable sets has a choice function.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

394

\(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

379

\(PKW(\infty,\infty,\infty)\): For every infinite family \(X\) of sets each of which has at least two elements, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in Y\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(y\).

167

\(PKW(\aleph_{0},\ge 2,\infty)\), Partial Kinna-Wagner Principle:  For every denumerable family \(F\) such that for all \(x\in F\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is an infinite subset \(H\subseteq F\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in H\), \(\emptyset\neq f(x) \subsetneq x\).

272

There is an \(X\subseteq{\Bbb R}\) such that neither \(X\) nor \(\Bbb R - X\) has a perfect subset.

169

There is an uncountable subset of \({\Bbb R}\) without a perfect subset.

52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

221

For all infinite \(X\), there is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

109

Every field \(F\) and every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that each linearly independent set \(A\subseteq V\) can be extended to a basis. H.Rubin/J.~Rubin [1985], pp 119ff.

236

If \(V\) is a vector space with a basis and \(S\) is a linearly independent subset of \(V\) such that no proper extension of \(S\) is a basis for \(V\), then \(S\) is a basis for \(V\).

327

\(KW(WO,<\aleph_0)\),  The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of finite sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

364

In \(\Bbb R\), there is a measurable set that is not Borel.  G. Moore [1982], p 325.

273

There is a subset of \({\Bbb R}\) which is not Borel.

358

\(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

374-n

\(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable.

288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

296

Part-\(\infty\): Every infinite set is the disjoint union of infinitely many infinite sets.

203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

306

The set of Vitali equivalence classes is linearly orderable. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow (\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y = q)\).).

305

There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Vitali equivalence classes. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).). \ac{Kanovei} \cite{1991}.

307

If \(m\) is the cardinality of the set of Vitali equivalence classes, then \(H(m) = H(2^{\aleph_0})\), where \(H\) is Hartogs aleph function and the {\it Vitali equivalence classes} are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in {\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).

311

Abelian groups are amenable. (\(G\) is amenable if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G)=1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

313

\(\Bbb Z\) (the set of integers under addition) is amenable.  (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

25

\(\aleph _{\beta +1}\) is regular for all ordinals \(\beta\).

315

\(\Omega = \omega_1\), where
\(\Omega = \{\alpha\in\hbox{ On}: (\forall\beta\le\alpha)(\beta=0 \vee (\exists\gamma)(\beta=\gamma+1) \vee\)
there is a sequence \(\langle\gamma_n: n\in\omega\rangle\) such that for each \(n\),
\(\gamma_n<\beta\hbox{ and } \beta=\bigcup_{n<\omega}\gamma_n.)\} \)

320

No successor cardinal, \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\), is measurable.

318

\(\aleph_1\) is not measurable.

320

No successor cardinal, \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\), is measurable.

321

There does not exist an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) is weakly compact and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) is measurable.

15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

398

\(KW(LO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered family of sets: For every linearly ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

399

\(KW(\infty,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a set of linearly orderable sets: For every set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

403

\(KW(LO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of well orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of well orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

327

\(KW(WO,<\aleph_0)\),  The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of finite sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

327

\(KW(WO,<\aleph_0)\),  The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of finite sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

401

\(KW(LO,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of finite sets: For every linearly ordered set of finite sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

327

\(KW(WO,<\aleph_0)\),  The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of finite sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

328

\(MC(WO,\infty)\): For  every well ordered set \(X\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that and for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\). (See Form 67.)

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

329

\(MC(\infty,WO)\): For  every set \(M\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

329

\(MC(\infty,WO)\): For  every set \(M\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

328

\(MC(WO,\infty)\): For  every well ordered set \(X\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that and for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\). (See Form 67.)

330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

396

\(MC(LO,WO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty well orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

397

\(MC(WO,LO)\): For each well ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

95-F

Existence of Complementary Subspaces over a Field \(F\): If \(F\) is a field, then every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that if \(S\subseteq V\) is a subspace of \(V\), then there is a subspace \(S'\subseteq V\) such that \(S\cap S'= \{0\}\) and \(S\cup S'\) generates \(V\). H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], pp 119ff, and Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.4.

333

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

333

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

378

Restricted Choice for Families of Well Ordered Sets:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that the family of non-empty well orderable subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

337

\(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered):  If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\).

394

\(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

337

\(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered):  If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\).

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

338

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,WO)\): The union of a denumerable number of denumerable sets is well orderable.

421
  \(UT(\aleph_0,WO,WO)\): The union of a denumerable set of well orderable sets can be well ordered.
338

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,WO)\): The union of a denumerable number of denumerable sets is well orderable.

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

339

Martin's Axiom \((\aleph_{0})\): Whenever \((P\le)\) is a non-empty, ccc  quasi-order (ccc means every anti-chain is countable) and \({\cal D}\) is a family of \(\le\aleph_0\) dense subsets of \(P\), then there is a \({\cal D}\) generic filter \(G\) in \(P\).

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

340

Every Lindelöf metric space is separable.

340

Every Lindelöf metric space is separable.

341

Every Lindelöf metric space is second countable.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

347

Idemmultiple Partition Principle: If \(y\) is idemmultiple (\(2\times y\approx y\)) and \(x\precsim ^* y\), then \(x\precsim y\).

85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

349

\(MC(\infty,\aleph_0)\): For every set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

329

\(MC(\infty,WO)\): For  every set \(M\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

349

\(MC(\infty,\aleph_0)\): For every set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

349

\(MC(\infty,\aleph_0)\): For every set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

355

\(KW(\aleph_0,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

355

\(KW(\aleph_0,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

356

  \(KW(\infty,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of denumerable sets: For every set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

357

\(KW(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of denumerable sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

357

\(KW(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of denumerable sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

355

\(KW(\aleph_0,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

357

\(KW(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of denumerable sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

356

  \(KW(\infty,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of denumerable sets: For every set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

357

\(KW(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of denumerable sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

327

\(KW(WO,<\aleph_0)\),  The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of finite sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

358

\(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

355

\(KW(\aleph_0,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

358

\(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

284

A system of linear equations over a field \(F\) has a solution in \(F\) if and only if every finite sub-system has a solution in \(F\).

360

A system of linear equations over the field \(\{0,1\}\) has a solution, if and only if every finite subsystem has a solution. Brunner [2001]

66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

367

There is a Hamel basis for \(\Bbb R\) as a vector space over \(\Bbb Q\).

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

368

The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

369

If \(\Bbb R\) is partitioned into two sets, at least one of them has cardinality \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

370

Weak Gelfand Extreme Point Theorem: If \(A\) is a non-trivial Gelfand algebra then the closed unit ball in the dual of \(A\) has an extreme point \(e\).  Morillon [1986].

288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

373-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\aleph_0,n,\infty)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

376

Restricted Kinna Wagner Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for every \(z\subseteq Y\), if \(|z| \ge 2\) then \(f(z)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(z\).

15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

376

Restricted Kinna Wagner Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for every \(z\subseteq Y\), if \(|z| \ge 2\) then \(f(z)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(z\).

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

377

Restricted Ordering Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that \(Y\) can be linearly ordered.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

378

Restricted Choice for Families of Well Ordered Sets:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that the family of non-empty well orderable subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

377

Restricted Ordering Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that \(Y\) can be linearly ordered.

378

Restricted Choice for Families of Well Ordered Sets:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that the family of non-empty well orderable subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

380

\(PC(\infty,WO,\infty)\):  For every infinite family of non-empty well orderable sets, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) which has a choice function.

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

380

\(PC(\infty,WO,\infty)\):  For every infinite family of non-empty well orderable sets, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) which has a choice function.

381

DUM:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

382

DUMN:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is normal.

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

385

Countable Ultrafilter Theorem:  Every proper filter with a countable base over a set \(S\) (in \({\cal P}(S)\)) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

389

\(C(\aleph_0,2,\cal P({\Bbb R}))\): Every denumerable family of two element subsets of \(\cal P({\Bbb R})\) has a choice function.  \ac{Keremedis} \cite{1999b}.

404

Every infinite set can be partitioned into infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

390

Every infinite set can be partitioned either into two infinite sets or infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

302

Any continuous surjection between compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

391

\(C(\infty,LO)\): Every set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

393

\(C(LO,WO)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty well orderable sets has a choice function.

112

\(MC(\infty,LO)\): For every family \(X\) of non-empty sets each of which can be linearly ordered there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

395

\(MC(LO,LO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

292

\(MC(LO,\infty)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

395

\(MC(LO,LO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

395

\(MC(LO,LO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

393

\(C(LO,WO)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty well orderable sets has a choice function.

396

\(MC(LO,WO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty well orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

395

\(MC(LO,LO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

396

\(MC(LO,WO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty well orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

395

\(MC(LO,LO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

397

\(MC(WO,LO)\): For each well ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

398

\(KW(LO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered family of sets: For every linearly ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

391

\(C(\infty,LO)\): Every set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

399

\(KW(\infty,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a set of linearly orderable sets: For every set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

398

\(KW(LO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered family of sets: For every linearly ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

401

\(KW(LO,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of finite sets: For every linearly ordered set of finite sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

401

\(KW(LO,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of finite sets: For every linearly ordered set of finite sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

394

\(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

402

\(KW(WO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every well ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

402

\(KW(WO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every well ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

403

\(KW(LO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of well orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of well orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

404

Every infinite set can be partitioned into infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

75

If a set has at least two elements, then it can be partitioned into well orderable subsets, each of which has at least two elements.

404

Every infinite set can be partitioned into infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

296

Part-\(\infty\): Every infinite set is the disjoint union of infinitely many infinite sets.

404

Every infinite set can be partitioned into infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

4

Every infinite set is the union of some disjoint family of denumerable subsets. (Denumerable means \(\cong \aleph_0\).)

405

Every infinite set can be partitioned into sets each of which is countable and has at least two elements.

411

RCuc (Reflexive Compactness for uniformly convex Banach spaces): The closed unit ball of a uniformly convex Banach space is compact for the weak topology.

412

RCh (Reflexive Compactness for Hilbert spaces): The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact for the weak topology.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

421
  \(UT(\aleph_0,WO,WO)\): The union of a denumerable set of well orderable sets can be well ordered.
10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

239

AL20(\(\mathbb Q\)):  Every vector \(V\) space over \(\mathbb Q\) has the property that every linearly independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis. Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p.119, AL20.

427
\(\exists F\) AL20(\(F\)): There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that every independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis.  \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, AL20}.
66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

428
\(\exists F\) B\((F)\):  There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space over \(F\) has a basis. \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

428
\(\exists F\) B\((F)\):  There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space over \(F\) has a basis. \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
427
\(\exists F\) AL20(\(F\)): There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that every independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis.  \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, AL20}.
428
\(\exists F\) B\((F)\):  There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space over \(F\) has a basis. \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
28-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) AL20(\(\mathbb Z_p\)): Every vector space \(V\) over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that every linearly independent subset can be extended to a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p. 119, Statement AL20

429-p
(Where \(p\) is a prime) B: Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
28-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) AL20(\(\mathbb Z_p\)): Every vector space \(V\) over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that every linearly independent subset can be extended to a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p. 119, Statement AL20

430-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) \(AL21\)\((p)\): Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that for every subspace \(S\) of \(V\), there is a subspace \(S'\) of \(V\) such that \(S \cap S' = \{ 0 \}\) and \(S \cup S'\) generates \(V\) in other words such that \(V = S \oplus S'\).   Rubin, H./Rubin, J [1985], p.119, AL21.

218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

430-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) \(AL21\)\((p)\): Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that for every subspace \(S\) of \(V\), there is a subspace \(S'\) of \(V\) such that \(S \cap S' = \{ 0 \}\) and \(S \cup S'\) generates \(V\) in other words such that \(V = S \oplus S'\).   Rubin, H./Rubin, J [1985], p.119, AL21.

31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

35

The union of countably many meager subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is meager. (Meager sets are the same as sets of the first category.) Jech [1973b] p 7 prob 1.7.

52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

287

The Hahn-Banach Theorem for Separable Normed Linear Spaces:  Assume \(V\) is a separable normed linear space and \(p :V \to \Bbb R\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t \ge 0)(\forall x \in V)(p(tx) = tp(x))\) and assume \(f\) is a linear function from a subspace \(S\) of \(V\) into \(\Bbb R\) which satisfies \((\forall x \in S)(f(x) \le p(x))\), then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^* :V \to \Bbb R\) so that \(f^* \) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^*(x) \le p(x))\).

47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

289

If \(S\) is a set of subsets of a countable set and \(S\) is closed under chain unions, then \(S\) has a \(\subseteq\)-maximal element.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

292

\(MC(LO,\infty)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

293

For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\) can be linearly ordered and there is a mapping of \(x\) onto \(y\), then \(y\) can be linearly ordered.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

294

Every linearly ordered \(W\)-set is well orderable.

129

For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) admits a partition into sets of order type \(\omega^{*} + \omega\). (For every infinite \(A\), there is a set \(\{\langle C_j,<_j \rangle: j\in J\}\) such that \(\{C_j: j\in J\}\) is a partition of \(A\) and for each \(j\in J\), \(<_j\) is an ordering of \(C_j\) of type \(\omega^* + \omega\).)

4

Every infinite set is the union of some disjoint family of denumerable subsets. (Denumerable means \(\cong \aleph_0\).)

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

39

\(C(\aleph_{1},\infty)\): Every set \(A\) of non-empty sets such that \(\vert A\vert = \aleph_{1}\) has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p. 202.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

86-alpha

\(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

181

\(C(2^{\aleph_0},\infty)\): Every set \(X\) of non-empty sets such that \(|X|=2^{\aleph_0}\) has a choice function.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

41

\(W_{\aleph _{1}}\): For every cardinal \(m\), \(m \le \aleph_{1}\) or \(\aleph_{1}\le m \).

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

129

For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) admits a partition into sets of order type \(\omega^{*} + \omega\). (For every infinite \(A\), there is a set \(\{\langle C_j,<_j \rangle: j\in J\}\) such that \(\{C_j: j\in J\}\) is a partition of \(A\) and for each \(j\in J\), \(<_j\) is an ordering of \(C_j\) of type \(\omega^* + \omega\).)

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

214

\(Z(\omega)\): For every family \(A\) of infinite sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in A\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty subset of \(y\) and \(|f(y)|=\aleph_{0}\).

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

185

Every linearly ordered Dedekind finite set is finite.

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

166

\(PC(\infty,2,\infty)\): Every infinite family of pairs has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

167

\(PKW(\aleph_{0},\ge 2,\infty)\), Partial Kinna-Wagner Principle:  For every denumerable family \(F\) such that for all \(x\in F\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is an infinite subset \(H\subseteq F\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in H\), \(\emptyset\neq f(x) \subsetneq x\).

18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

21

If \(S\) is well ordered, \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets, and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}|= |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). G\.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

24

\(C(\aleph_0,2^{(2^{\aleph_0})})\): Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets each with power \(2^{(2^{\aleph_{0}})}\) has a choice function.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

27

\((\forall \alpha)( UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): The  union of denumerably many sets each of power \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) has power \(\aleph_{\alpha}\). Moore, G. [1982], p 36.

23

\((\forall \alpha)(UT(\aleph_{\alpha},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): For every ordinal \(\alpha\), if \(A\) and every member of \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\), then \(|\bigcup A| = \aleph _{\alpha }\).

27

\((\forall \alpha)( UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): The  union of denumerably many sets each of power \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) has power \(\aleph_{\alpha}\). Moore, G. [1982], p 36.

20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

29
 If \(|S| = \aleph_{0}\) and \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} A_{x}| = |\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore, G. [1982], p 324.

21

If \(S\) is well ordered, \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets, and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}|= |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). G\.

29
 If \(|S| = \aleph_{0}\) and \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} A_{x}| = |\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore, G. [1982], p 324.

49

Order Extension Principle: Every partial ordering can be extended to a linear ordering.  Tarski [1924], p 78.

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

33-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,n)\):  Every linearly ordered set of \(n\) element sets has  a choice function.

25

\(\aleph _{\beta +1}\) is regular for all ordinals \(\beta\).

34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

39

\(C(\aleph_{1},\infty)\): Every set \(A\) of non-empty sets such that \(\vert A\vert = \aleph_{1}\) has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p. 202.

202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

46-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,K)\): For every \(n\in K\), every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

46-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,K)\): For every \(n\in K\), every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

33-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,n)\):  Every linearly ordered set of \(n\) element sets has  a choice function.

47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

46-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,K)\): For every \(n\in K\), every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

48-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,K)\): For every \(n\in K,\) \(C(WO,n)\).

120-K

If \(K\subseteq\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,K)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty sets each of whose cardinality is in \(K\) has a choice function.

48-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,K)\): For every \(n\in K,\) \(C(WO,n)\).

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

48-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,K)\): For every \(n\in K,\) \(C(WO,n)\).

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

57

If \(x\) and \(y\) are Dedekind finite sets then either \(|x|\le |y|\) or \(|y|\le |x|\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

208

For all ordinals \(\alpha\), \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\le 2^{\aleph_\alpha}\).

58

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\neq\aleph_{\alpha +1}\). (\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}})\) is Hartogs' aleph, the least \(\aleph\) not \(\le 2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\).)
Mathias [1979], p 126.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

107
 

M. Hall's Theorem: Let \(\{S(\alpha): \alpha\in A\}\) be a collection of finite subsets (of a set \(X\)) then if

(*) for each finite \(F \subseteq  A\) there is an injective choice function on \(F\)
then there is an injective choice function on \(A\). (That is, a 1-1 function \(f\) such that \((\forall\alpha\in A)(f(\alpha)\in S(\alpha))\).) (According to a theorem of P. Hall (\(*\)) is equivalent to \(\left |\bigcup_{\alpha\in F} S(\alpha)\right|\ge |F|\). P. Hall's theorem does not require the axiom of choice.)

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

63

\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
Jech [1973b], p 172 prob 8.5.

123

\(SPI^*\): Uniform weak ultrafilter principle: For each family \(F\) of infinite sets \(\exists f\) such that \(\forall x\in F\), \(f(x)\) is a non-principal ultrafilter on \(x\).

63

\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
Jech [1973b], p 172 prob 8.5.

218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

225

Every proper filter on \(\omega\) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

6

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): The union of a denumerable  family  of denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is denumerable.

6

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): The union of a denumerable  family  of denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is denumerable.

Moore-1982,
13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

Moore-1982,
16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

Moore-1982,
21

If \(S\) is well ordered, \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets, and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}|= |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). G\.

21

If \(S\) is well ordered, \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets, and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}|= |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). G\.

Moore-1982,
21

If \(S\) is well ordered, \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets, and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}|= |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). G\.

23

\((\forall \alpha)(UT(\aleph_{\alpha},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): For every ordinal \(\alpha\), if \(A\) and every member of \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\), then \(|\bigcup A| = \aleph _{\alpha }\).

Moore-1982,
23

\((\forall \alpha)(UT(\aleph_{\alpha},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): For every ordinal \(\alpha\), if \(A\) and every member of \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\), then \(|\bigcup A| = \aleph _{\alpha }\).

23

\((\forall \alpha)(UT(\aleph_{\alpha},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): For every ordinal \(\alpha\), if \(A\) and every member of \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\), then \(|\bigcup A| = \aleph _{\alpha }\).

Moore-1982,
24

\(C(\aleph_0,2^{(2^{\aleph_0})})\): Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets each with power \(2^{(2^{\aleph_{0}})}\) has a choice function.

24

\(C(\aleph_0,2^{(2^{\aleph_0})})\): Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets each with power \(2^{(2^{\aleph_{0}})}\) has a choice function.

Moore-1982,
60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

Moore-1982-5
42

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem: If a countable family of first order  sentences is satisfiable in a set \(M\) then it is satisfiable in a countable subset of \(M\). (See Moore, G. [1982], p. 251 for references.

42

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem: If a countable family of first order  sentences is satisfiable in a set \(M\) then it is satisfiable in a countable subset of \(M\). (See Moore, G. [1982], p. 251 for references.

Moore-1982-7
29
 If \(|S| = \aleph_{0}\) and \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} A_{x}| = |\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore, G. [1982], p 324.

31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

Moore-1982-2
9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Moore-1982-8
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

29
 If \(|S| = \aleph_{0}\) and \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} A_{x}| = |\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore, G. [1982], p 324.

Moore-1982-9
29
 If \(|S| = \aleph_{0}\) and \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} A_{x}| = |\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore, G. [1982], p 324.

29
 If \(|S| = \aleph_{0}\) and \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} A_{x}| = |\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore, G. [1982], p 324.

Moore-1982-9
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

361

In \(\Bbb R\), the union of a denumerable number of analytic sets is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

Moore-1982-10
361

In \(\Bbb R\), the union of a denumerable number of analytic sets is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

362

In \(\Bbb R\), every Borel set is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

Moore-1982-10
363

There are exactly \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Borel sets in \(\Bbb R\). G. Moore [1982], p 325.

364

In \(\Bbb R\), there is a measurable set that is not Borel.  G. Moore [1982], p 325.

Moore-1982-10
40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

Moore-1982-10
41

\(W_{\aleph _{1}}\): For every cardinal \(m\), \(m \le \aleph_{1}\) or \(\aleph_{1}\le m \).

41

\(W_{\aleph _{1}}\): For every cardinal \(m\), \(m \le \aleph_{1}\) or \(\aleph_{1}\le m \).

Moore-1982-11
27

\((\forall \alpha)( UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): The  union of denumerably many sets each of power \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) has power \(\aleph_{\alpha}\). Moore, G. [1982], p 36.

27

\((\forall \alpha)( UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): The  union of denumerably many sets each of power \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) has power \(\aleph_{\alpha}\). Moore, G. [1982], p 36.

Moore-1982-3
366

There is a discontinuous function \(f: \Bbb R \to\Bbb R\) such that for all real \(x\) and \(y\), \(f(x+y)=f(x)+f(y)\).

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Moore-1982-12
41

\(W_{\aleph _{1}}\): For every cardinal \(m\), \(m \le \aleph_{1}\) or \(\aleph_{1}\le m \).

365

For every uncountable set \(A\), if \(A\) has the same cardinality as each of its uncountable subsets then \(|A| = \aleph_1\).

Moore-1982-12
195

Every general linear system has a linear global reaction.

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

Keremedis-2001a,
346

If \(V\) is a vector space without a finite basis then \(V\) contains an infinite, well ordered, linearly independent subset.

18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

Keremedis-2001a,
346

If \(V\) is a vector space without a finite basis then \(V\) contains an infinite, well ordered, linearly independent subset.

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

Keremedis-2001a,
66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

346

If \(V\) is a vector space without a finite basis then \(V\) contains an infinite, well ordered, linearly independent subset.

Keremedis-2001a,
110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

373-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\aleph_0,n,\infty)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

Keremedis-2001a,
346

If \(V\) is a vector space without a finite basis then \(V\) contains an infinite, well ordered, linearly independent subset.

373-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\aleph_0,n,\infty)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

Keremedis-2001a,
94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

74

For every \(A\subseteq\Bbb R\) the following are equivalent:

  1. \(A\) is closed and bounded.
  2. Every sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subseteq A\) has a convergent subsequence with limit in A.
Jech [1973b], p 21.

Note 10,
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

Note 123,
375

Tietze-Urysohn Extension Theorem: If \((X,T)\) is a normal topological space, \(A\) is closed in \(X\), and \(f: A\to [0,1]\) is continuous, then there exists a continuous function \(g: X\to [0,1]\) which extends \(f\).

119

van Douwen's choice principle: \(C(\aleph_{0}\),uniformly orderable with order type of the integers): Suppose \(\{ A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) is a set and there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(i\in\omega,\ f(i)\) is an ordering of \(A_{i}\) of type \(\omega^{*}+\omega\) (the usual ordering of the integers), then \(\{A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) has a choice function.

Note 138,
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

375

Tietze-Urysohn Extension Theorem: If \((X,T)\) is a normal topological space, \(A\) is closed in \(X\), and \(f: A\to [0,1]\) is continuous, then there exists a continuous function \(g: X\to [0,1]\) which extends \(f\).

Note 139,
214

\(Z(\omega)\): For every family \(A\) of infinite sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in A\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty subset of \(y\) and \(|f(y)|=\aleph_{0}\).

152

\(D_{\aleph_{0}}\): Every non-well-orderable set is the union of a pairwise disjoint, well orderable family of denumerable sets.  (See note 27 for \(D_{\kappa}\), \(\kappa\) a well ordered cardinal.)

Note 140,
234

There is a non-Ramsey set: There is a set \(A\) of infinite subsets of \(\omega\) such that for every infinite subset \(N\) of \(\omega\), \(N\) has a subset which is in \(A\) and a subset which is not in \(A\).

282

\(\omega\not\to(\omega)^{\omega}\).

Note 142,
385

Countable Ultrafilter Theorem:  Every proper filter with a countable base over a set \(S\) (in \({\cal P}(S)\)) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

Note 150,
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

340

Every Lindelöf metric space is separable.

Note 157,
341

Every Lindelöf metric space is second countable.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

Note 158,
319

Measurable cardinals are inaccessible.

320

No successor cardinal, \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\), is measurable.

Note 20,
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

410

RC (Reflexive Compactness): The closed unit ball of a reflexive normed space is compact for the weak topology.

Note 23,
284

A system of linear equations over a field \(F\) has a solution in \(F\) if and only if every finite sub-system has a solution in \(F\).

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

Note 36,
9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

325

Ramsey's Theorem II: \(\forall n,m\in\omega\), if A is an infinite set and the family of all \(m\) element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into \(n\) sets \(S_{j}, 1\le j\le n\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all \(m\) element subsets of \(B\) belong to the same \(S_{j}\). (Also, see Form 17.)

Note 46,
203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

Note 67,
3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
53

For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(m^2\le 2^m\).  Mathias [1979], prob 1336.

Note 68,
40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

208

For all ordinals \(\alpha\), \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\le 2^{\aleph_\alpha}\).

Note 69,
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

113

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many Spaces: The product of a countable set of compact spaces is compact.

Note 7,
323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

Note 70,
26

\(UT(\aleph_{0},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): The union of denumerably many sets each of power \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

209

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that for all \(X\), if \(X\) is a denumerable union of denumerable sets then \({\cal P}(X)\) cannot be partitioned into \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) non-empty sets.

Note 72,
31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

209

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that for all \(X\), if \(X\) is a denumerable union of denumerable sets then \({\cal P}(X)\) cannot be partitioned into \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) non-empty sets.

Note 72,
207-alpha

\(UT(\aleph_{\alpha },\aleph_{\alpha}, <2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\): The union of \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) sets each of cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) has cardinality less than \(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}}\).

209

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that for all \(X\), if \(X\) is a denumerable union of denumerable sets then \({\cal P}(X)\) cannot be partitioned into \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) non-empty sets.

Note 72,
202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

Note 75,
126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

Note 76,
126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

185

Every linearly ordered Dedekind finite set is finite.

Note 76,
30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

83

\(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite.

Note 81,
106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

Goldblatt-1985,
170

\(\aleph_{1}\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

Moore-1982,
52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

Pincus-1972c,
90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

118

Every linearly orderable topological space is normal.  Birkhoff [1967], p 241.

van Douwen-1985,
118

Every linearly orderable topological space is normal.  Birkhoff [1967], p 241.

119

van Douwen's choice principle: \(C(\aleph_{0}\),uniformly orderable with order type of the integers): Suppose \(\{ A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) is a set and there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(i\in\omega,\ f(i)\) is an ordering of \(A_{i}\) of type \(\omega^{*}+\omega\) (the usual ordering of the integers), then \(\{A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) has a choice function.

van Douwen-1985,
119

van Douwen's choice principle: \(C(\aleph_{0}\),uniformly orderable with order type of the integers): Suppose \(\{ A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) is a set and there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(i\in\omega,\ f(i)\) is an ordering of \(A_{i}\) of type \(\omega^{*}+\omega\) (the usual ordering of the integers), then \(\{A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) has a choice function.

119

van Douwen's choice principle: \(C(\aleph_{0}\),uniformly orderable with order type of the integers): Suppose \(\{ A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) is a set and there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(i\in\omega,\ f(i)\) is an ordering of \(A_{i}\) of type \(\omega^{*}+\omega\) (the usual ordering of the integers), then \(\{A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) has a choice function.

van Douwen-1985,
174-alpha

\(RM1,\aleph_{\alpha }\): The representation theorem for multi-algebras with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations:  Assume \((A,F)\) is  a  multi-algebra  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations (and no other operations). Then  there  is  an  algebra \((B,G)\)  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations and an equivalence relation \(E\) on \(B\) such that \((B/E,G/E)\) and \((A,F)\) are isomorphic multi-algebras.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

van Douwen-1985, Note 49,
175

Transitivity Condition: For all sets \(x\), there is a set \(u\) and a function \(f\) such that \(u\) is transitive and \(f\) is a one to one function from \(x\) onto \(u\).

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

van Douwen-1985, Note 49,
61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

213

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{1})\): If \((\forall y\in X)(|y| = \aleph_{1})\) then \(X\) has a choice function.

85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

86-alpha

\(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function.

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

212

\(C(2^{\aleph_{0}},\subseteq{\Bbb R})\): If \(R\) is a relation on \({\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), there is a \(y\in{\Bbb R}\) such that \(x\mathrel R y\), then there is a function \(f: {\Bbb R} \rightarrow{\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), \(x\mathrel R f(x)\).

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

98

The set of all finite subsets of a Dedekind finite set is Dedekind finite. Jech [1973b] p 161 prob 11.5.

101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

168

Dual Cantor-Bernstein Theorem:\((\forall x) (\forall y)(|x| \le^*|y|\) and \(|y|\le^* |x|\) implies  \(|x| = |y|)\) .

100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

159

The regular cardinals are cofinal in the class of ordinals.

104

There is a regular uncountable aleph. Jech [1966b], p 165 prob 11.26.

59-le

If \((A,\le)\) is a partial ordering that is not a well ordering, then there is no set \(B\) such that \((B,\le)\) (the usual injective cardinal ordering on \(B\)) is isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).
Mathias [1979], p 120.

105

There is a  partially ordered set \((A,\le)\) such that for no set \(B\) is \((B,\le)\) (the ordering  on \(B\) is the usual injective cardinal ordering) isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).

38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

108

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\) is not the union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets.

207-alpha

\(UT(\aleph_{\alpha },\aleph_{\alpha}, <2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\): The union of \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) sets each of cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) has cardinality less than \(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}}\).

108

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\) is not the union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

112

\(MC(\infty,LO)\): For every family \(X\) of non-empty sets each of which can be linearly ordered there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

46-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,K)\): For every \(n\in K\), every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

120-K

If \(K\subseteq\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,K)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty sets each of whose cardinality is in \(K\) has a choice function.

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

120-K

If \(K\subseteq\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,K)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty sets each of whose cardinality is in \(K\) has a choice function.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

140

Let \(\Omega\) be the set of all (undirected) infinite cycles of reals (Graphs whose vertices are real numbers, connected, no loops and each vertex adjacent to  exactly two others). Then there is a function \(f\) on \(\Omega \) such that for all \(s\in\Omega\), \(f(s)\) is a direction along \(s\).

23

\((\forall \alpha)(UT(\aleph_{\alpha},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): For every ordinal \(\alpha\), if \(A\) and every member of \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\), then \(|\bigcup A| = \aleph _{\alpha }\).

151

\(UT(WO,\aleph_{0},WO)\) (\(U_{\aleph_{1}}\)): The union of a well ordered set of denumerable sets is well  orderable. (If \(\kappa\) is a well ordered cardinal, see note 27 for \(UT(WO,\kappa,WO)\).)

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

151

\(UT(WO,\aleph_{0},WO)\) (\(U_{\aleph_{1}}\)): The union of a well ordered set of denumerable sets is well  orderable. (If \(\kappa\) is a well ordered cardinal, see note 27 for \(UT(WO,\kappa,WO)\).)

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

178-n-N

If  \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\) and \(N \subseteq \{ 1, 2, \ldots , n-1 \}\), \(N \neq\emptyset\), \(MC(\infty,n, N)\):  If \(X\) is any set of \(n\)-element sets then  there is  a function \(f\) with domain \(X\) such that for all \(A\in X\), \(f(A)\subseteq A\) and \(|f(A)|\in N\).

202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

181

\(C(2^{\aleph_0},\infty)\): Every set \(X\) of non-empty sets such that \(|X|=2^{\aleph_0}\) has a choice function.

104

There is a regular uncountable aleph. Jech [1966b], p 165 prob 11.26.

182

There is an aleph whose cofinality is greater than \(\aleph_{0}\).

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

185

Every linearly ordered Dedekind finite set is finite.

16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

194

\(C(\varPi^1_2)\) or \(AC(\varPi^1_2)\): If \(P\in \omega\times{}^{\omega}\omega\), \(P\) has domain \(\omega\), and \(P\) is in \(\varPi^1_2\), then there is a sequence of elements \(\langle x_{k}: k\in\omega\rangle\) of \({}^{\omega}\omega\) with \(\langle k,x_{k}\rangle \in P\) for all \(k\in\omega\). Kanovei [1979].

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

194

\(C(\varPi^1_2)\) or \(AC(\varPi^1_2)\): If \(P\in \omega\times{}^{\omega}\omega\), \(P\) has domain \(\omega\), and \(P\) is in \(\varPi^1_2\), then there is a sequence of elements \(\langle x_{k}: k\in\omega\rangle\) of \({}^{\omega}\omega\) with \(\langle k,x_{k}\rangle \in P\) for all \(k\in\omega\). Kanovei [1979].

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

198

For every set \(S\), if the only linearly orderable subsets of \(S\) are the finite subsets of \(S\), then either \(S\) is finite or \(S\) has an amorphous subset.

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

198

For every set \(S\), if the only linearly orderable subsets of \(S\) are the finite subsets of \(S\), then either \(S\) is finite or \(S\) has an amorphous subset.

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

199(\(n\))

(For \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\)) If all \(\varSigma^{1}_{n}\), Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega }\omega\) are finite, then all \(\varPi^1_n\) Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega} \omega\) are finite.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
204

For every infinite \(X\), there is a function from \(X\) onto \(2X\).

70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

206

The existence of a non-principal ultrafilter: There exists an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal ultrafilter on \(X\).

68

Nielsen-Schreier Theorem: Every subgroup of a free group is free.  Jech [1973b], p 12.

210

The commutator subgroup of a free group is free.

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

212

\(C(2^{\aleph_{0}},\subseteq{\Bbb R})\): If \(R\) is a relation on \({\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), there is a \(y\in{\Bbb R}\) such that \(x\mathrel R y\), then there is a function \(f: {\Bbb R} \rightarrow{\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), \(x\mathrel R f(x)\).

211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

212

\(C(2^{\aleph_{0}},\subseteq{\Bbb R})\): If \(R\) is a relation on \({\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), there is a \(y\in{\Bbb R}\) such that \(x\mathrel R y\), then there is a function \(f: {\Bbb R} \rightarrow{\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), \(x\mathrel R f(x)\).

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

213

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{1})\): If \((\forall y\in X)(|y| = \aleph_{1})\) then \(X\) has a choice function.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

217

Every infinite partially ordered set has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

63

\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
Jech [1973b], p 172 prob 8.5.

221

For all infinite \(X\), there is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

221

For all infinite \(X\), there is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

206

The existence of a non-principal ultrafilter: There exists an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal ultrafilter on \(X\).

223

There is an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

223

There is an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

242

There is, up to an isomorphism, at most one algebraic closure of \({\Bbb Q}\).

241

Every algebraic closure of \(\Bbb Q\) has a real closed subfield.

233

Artin-Schreier theorem: If a field has an algebraic closure it is unique up to isomorphism.

242

There is, up to an isomorphism, at most one algebraic closure of \({\Bbb Q}\).

278

In an integral domain \(R\), if every ideal is finitely generated then \(R\) has a maximal proper ideal. note 45 E.

244

Every principal ideal domain has a maximal ideal.

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

338

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,WO)\): The union of a denumerable number of denumerable sets is well orderable.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

337

\(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered):  If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\).

92

\(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

Levy-1958,
427
\(\exists F\) AL20(\(F\)): There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that every independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis.  \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, AL20}.
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

379

\(PKW(\infty,\infty,\infty)\): For every infinite family \(X\) of sets each of which has at least two elements, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in Y\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(y\).

218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

95-F

Existence of Complementary Subspaces over a Field \(F\): If \(F\) is a field, then every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that if \(S\subseteq V\) is a subspace of \(V\), then there is a subspace \(S'\subseteq V\) such that \(S\cap S'= \{0\}\) and \(S\cup S'\) generates \(V\). H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], pp 119ff, and Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.4.

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

107
 

M. Hall's Theorem: Let \(\{S(\alpha): \alpha\in A\}\) be a collection of finite subsets (of a set \(X\)) then if

(*) for each finite \(F \subseteq  A\) there is an injective choice function on \(F\)
then there is an injective choice function on \(A\). (That is, a 1-1 function \(f\) such that \((\forall\alpha\in A)(f(\alpha)\in S(\alpha))\).) (According to a theorem of P. Hall (\(*\)) is equivalent to \(\left |\bigcup_{\alpha\in F} S(\alpha)\right|\ge |F|\). P. Hall's theorem does not require the axiom of choice.)

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

139

Using the discrete topology on 2, \(2^{\cal P(\omega)}\) is compact.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

216

Every infinite tree has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

287

The Hahn-Banach Theorem for Separable Normed Linear Spaces:  Assume \(V\) is a separable normed linear space and \(p :V \to \Bbb R\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t \ge 0)(\forall x \in V)(p(tx) = tp(x))\) and assume \(f\) is a linear function from a subspace \(S\) of \(V\) into \(\Bbb R\) which satisfies \((\forall x \in S)(f(x) \le p(x))\), then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^* :V \to \Bbb R\) so that \(f^* \) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^*(x) \le p(x))\).

222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

249

If \(T\) is an infinite tree in which every element has exactly 2 immediate successors then \(T\) has an infinite branch.

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

375

Tietze-Urysohn Extension Theorem: If \((X,T)\) is a normal topological space, \(A\) is closed in \(X\), and \(f: A\to [0,1]\) is continuous, then there exists a continuous function \(g: X\to [0,1]\) which extends \(f\).

374-n

\(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable.

423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

4

Every infinite set is the union of some disjoint family of denumerable subsets. (Denumerable means \(\cong \aleph_0\).)

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

109

Every field \(F\) and every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that each linearly independent set \(A\subseteq V\) can be extended to a basis. H.Rubin/J.~Rubin [1985], pp 119ff.

28-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) AL20(\(\mathbb Z_p\)): Every vector space \(V\) over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that every linearly independent subset can be extended to a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p. 119, Statement AL20

407

Let \(B\) be a Boolean algebra, \(b\) a non-zero element of \(B\) and \(\{A_i: i\in\omega\}\) a sequence of subsets of \(B\) such that for each \(i\in\omega\), \(A_i\) has a supremum \(a_i\). Then there exists an ultrafilter \(D\) in \(B\) such that \(b\in D\) and, for each \(i\in\omega\), if \(a_i\in D\), then \(D\cap\ A_i\neq\emptyset\).

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

422-n

\(UT(WO,n,WO)\), \(n\in \omega-\{0,1\}\): The union of a well ordered set of \(n\) element sets can be well ordered.

47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

109

Every field \(F\) and every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that each linearly independent set \(A\subseteq V\) can be extended to a basis. H.Rubin/J.~Rubin [1985], pp 119ff.

66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

333

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

359

If \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| \le |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| \le |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\).

101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

115

The product of weakly Loeb \(T_2\) spaces is weakly Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

131

\(MC_\omega(\aleph_0,\infty)\): For every denumerable family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

113

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many Spaces: The product of a countable set of compact spaces is compact.

154

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many \(T_2\) Spaces: The product of countably many \(T_2\) compact spaces is compact.

376

Restricted Kinna Wagner Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for every \(z\subseteq Y\), if \(|z| \ge 2\) then \(f(z)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(z\).

167

\(PKW(\aleph_{0},\ge 2,\infty)\), Partial Kinna-Wagner Principle:  For every denumerable family \(F\) such that for all \(x\in F\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is an infinite subset \(H\subseteq F\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in H\), \(\emptyset\neq f(x) \subsetneq x\).

109

Every field \(F\) and every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that each linearly independent set \(A\subseteq V\) can be extended to a basis. H.Rubin/J.~Rubin [1985], pp 119ff.

239

AL20(\(\mathbb Q\)):  Every vector \(V\) space over \(\mathbb Q\) has the property that every linearly independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis. Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p.119, AL20.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

304

There does not exist a \(T_2\) topological space \(X\) such that every infinite subset of \(X\) contains an infinite compact subset.

117

If \(\kappa\) is a measurable cardinal, then \(\kappa\) is the \(\kappa\)th inaccessible cardinal.

319

Measurable cardinals are inaccessible.

15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

402

\(KW(WO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every well ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

328

\(MC(WO,\infty)\): For  every well ordered set \(X\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that and for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\). (See Form 67.)

329

\(MC(\infty,WO)\): For  every set \(M\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

12

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\) and every \(n\in\omega\), there is an infinite subset \(B\) of \(A\) such the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco} [1998b]

336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

338

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,WO)\): The union of a denumerable number of denumerable sets is well orderable.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

341

Every Lindelöf metric space is second countable.

73

\(\forall n\in\omega\), \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  For every \(n\in\omega\), if \(C\) is an infinite family of \(n\) element sets, then \(C\) has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

356

  \(KW(\infty,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of denumerable sets: For every set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

358

\(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

363

There are exactly \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Borel sets in \(\Bbb R\). G. Moore [1982], p 325.

368

The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

373-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\aleph_0,n,\infty)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

374-n

\(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable.

15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

379

\(PKW(\infty,\infty,\infty)\): For every infinite family \(X\) of sets each of which has at least two elements, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in Y\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(y\).

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

390

Every infinite set can be partitioned either into two infinite sets or infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

394

\(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

394

\(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

397

\(MC(WO,LO)\): For each well ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

399

\(KW(\infty,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a set of linearly orderable sets: For every set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

393

\(C(LO,WO)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty well orderable sets has a choice function.

403

\(KW(LO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of well orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of well orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

410

RC (Reflexive Compactness): The closed unit ball of a reflexive normed space is compact for the weak topology.

411

RCuc (Reflexive Compactness for uniformly convex Banach spaces): The closed unit ball of a uniformly convex Banach space is compact for the weak topology.

28-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) AL20(\(\mathbb Z_p\)): Every vector space \(V\) over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that every linearly independent subset can be extended to a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p. 119, Statement AL20

427
\(\exists F\) AL20(\(F\)): There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that every independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis.  \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, AL20}.
429-p
(Where \(p\) is a prime) B: Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
428
\(\exists F\) B\((F)\):  There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space over \(F\) has a basis. \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

280

There is a complete separable metric space with a subset which does not have the Baire property.

31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

6

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): The union of a denumerable  family  of denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is denumerable.

71-alpha
 

\(W_{\aleph_{\alpha}}\): \((\forall x)(|x|\le\aleph_{\alpha }\) or \(|x|\ge \aleph_{\alpha})\). Jech [1973b], page 119.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

22

\(UT(2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): If every member of an infinite  set of cardinality \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\), then the union has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

26

\(UT(\aleph_{0},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): The union of denumerably many sets each of power \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

27

\((\forall \alpha)( UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): The  union of denumerably many sets each of power \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) has power \(\aleph_{\alpha}\). Moore, G. [1982], p 36.

31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

33-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,n)\):  Every linearly ordered set of \(n\) element sets has  a choice function.

87-alpha

\(DC(\aleph_{\alpha})\): Given a relation \(R\) such that for every subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\), there is an \(x\in X\) with \(Y\mathrel R x\) then there is a function \(f:\aleph_{\alpha}\to X\) such that (\(\forall\beta < \aleph_{\alpha}\)) \(\{f(\gamma): \gamma < \beta\}\mathrel R f(\beta)\).

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

48-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,K)\): For every \(n\in K,\) \(C(WO,n)\).

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

63

\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
Jech [1973b], p 172 prob 8.5.

70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

130

\({\cal P}(\Bbb R)\) is well orderable.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

215

If \((\forall y\subseteq X)(y\) can be linearly ordered implies \(y\) is finite), then \(X\) is finite.

83

\(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

104

There is a regular uncountable aleph. Jech [1966b], p 165 prob 11.26.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

119

van Douwen's choice principle: \(C(\aleph_{0}\),uniformly orderable with order type of the integers): Suppose \(\{ A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) is a set and there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(i\in\omega,\ f(i)\) is an ordering of \(A_{i}\) of type \(\omega^{*}+\omega\) (the usual ordering of the integers), then \(\{A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) has a choice function.

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

179-epsilon

Suppose  \(\epsilon > 0\) is an ordinal. \(\forall x\), \(x\in W(\epsilon\)).

144

Every set is almost well orderable.

71-alpha
 

\(W_{\aleph_{\alpha}}\): \((\forall x)(|x|\le\aleph_{\alpha }\) or \(|x|\ge \aleph_{\alpha})\). Jech [1973b], page 119.

183-alpha

There are no \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) minimal  sets.  That is, there are no sets \(X\) such that

  1. \(|X|\) is incomparable with \(\aleph_{\alpha}\)
  2. \(\aleph_{\beta}<|X|\) for every \(\beta < \alpha \) and
  3. \(\forall Y\subseteq X, |Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\) or \(|X-Y| <\aleph_{\alpha}\).

215

If \((\forall y\subseteq X)(y\) can be linearly ordered implies \(y\) is finite), then \(X\) is finite.

198

For every set \(S\), if the only linearly orderable subsets of \(S\) are the finite subsets of \(S\), then either \(S\) is finite or \(S\) has an amorphous subset.

23

\((\forall \alpha)(UT(\aleph_{\alpha},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): For every ordinal \(\alpha\), if \(A\) and every member of \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\), then \(|\bigcup A| = \aleph _{\alpha }\).

207-alpha

\(UT(\aleph_{\alpha },\aleph_{\alpha}, <2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\): The union of \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) sets each of cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) has cardinality less than \(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}}\).

217

Every infinite partially ordered set has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

216

Every infinite tree has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

96

Löwig's Theorem:If \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are both bases for the vector space \(V\) then \(|B_{1}| = |B_{2}|\).

235

If \(V\) is a vector space and \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are bases for \(V\) then \(|B_{1}|\) and \(|B_{2}|\) are comparable.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
0
 \(0 = 0\).
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

2

Existence of successor cardinals: For every cardinal \(m\) there is a cardinal \(n\) such that \(m < n\) and \((\forall p < n)(p \le m)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

4

Every infinite set is the union of some disjoint family of denumerable subsets. (Denumerable means \(\cong \aleph_0\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

6

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): The union of a denumerable  family  of denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is denumerable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

7

There is no infinite decreasing sequence of cardinals.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

11

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) has an infinite subset \(B\) such that for every \(n\in\omega\), \(n>0\), the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

12

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\) and every \(n\in\omega\), there is an infinite subset \(B\) of \(A\) such the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco} [1998b]

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

19

A real function is analytically representable if and only if it is in Baire's classification. G.Moore [1982], equation (2.3.1).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

21

If \(S\) is well ordered, \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets, and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}|= |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). G\.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

22

\(UT(2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): If every member of an infinite  set of cardinality \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\), then the union has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

23

\((\forall \alpha)(UT(\aleph_{\alpha},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): For every ordinal \(\alpha\), if \(A\) and every member of \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\), then \(|\bigcup A| = \aleph _{\alpha }\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

24

\(C(\aleph_0,2^{(2^{\aleph_0})})\): Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets each with power \(2^{(2^{\aleph_{0}})}\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

25

\(\aleph _{\beta +1}\) is regular for all ordinals \(\beta\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

26

\(UT(\aleph_{0},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): The union of denumerably many sets each of power \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

27

\((\forall \alpha)( UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): The  union of denumerably many sets each of power \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) has power \(\aleph_{\alpha}\). Moore, G. [1982], p 36.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

28-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) AL20(\(\mathbb Z_p\)): Every vector space \(V\) over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that every linearly independent subset can be extended to a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p. 119, Statement AL20

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

29
 If \(|S| = \aleph_{0}\) and \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} A_{x}| = |\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore, G. [1982], p 324.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

33-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,n)\):  Every linearly ordered set of \(n\) element sets has  a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

35

The union of countably many meager subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is meager. (Meager sets are the same as sets of the first category.) Jech [1973b] p 7 prob 1.7.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

36

Compact T\(_2\) spaces are Loeb. (A space is Loeb if the set of non-empty closed sets has a choice function.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

37

Lebesgue measure is countably additive.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

39

\(C(\aleph_{1},\infty)\): Every set \(A\) of non-empty sets such that \(\vert A\vert = \aleph_{1}\) has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p. 202.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

41

\(W_{\aleph _{1}}\): For every cardinal \(m\), \(m \le \aleph_{1}\) or \(\aleph_{1}\le m \).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

42

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem: If a countable family of first order  sentences is satisfiable in a set \(M\) then it is satisfiable in a countable subset of \(M\). (See Moore, G. [1982], p. 251 for references.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

44

\(DC(\aleph _{1})\):  Given a relation \(R\) such that for every  subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y| < \aleph_{1}\) there is an \(x \in  X\)  with \(Y \mathrel R x\), then there is a function \(f: \aleph_{1} \rightarrow  X\) such that \((\forall\beta < \aleph_{1}) (\{f(\gamma ): \gamma < b \} \mathrel R f(\beta))\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

46-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,K)\): For every \(n\in K\), every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

48-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,K)\): For every \(n\in K,\) \(C(WO,n)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

49

Order Extension Principle: Every partial ordering can be extended to a linear ordering.  Tarski [1924], p 78.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

50

Sikorski's  Extension Theorem: Every homomorphism of a subalgebra \(B\) of a Boolean algebra \(A\) into a complete Boolean algebra \(B'\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B'\). Sikorski [1964], p. 141.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

53

For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(m^2\le 2^m\).  Mathias [1979], prob 1336.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

54

For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(m\) adj \(2^{m}\) implies \(m\) is an aleph.  
Note that \(m\) adj \(n\) iff \(m < n\) and \(\neg (\exists p) (m < p < n).\)
Mathias [1979] prob 1337, thm 1338 and prob 1339.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

55

For all infinite cardinals \(m\) and \(n\), if \(m\cdot n = m + n\) then, \(m \le  n\) or \(n \le m\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

56

\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{0}})\neq\aleph_{\omega}\). (\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{0}})\) is Hartogs' aleph, the least \(\aleph\) not \(\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).)
Mathias [1979], p 125.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

57

If \(x\) and \(y\) are Dedekind finite sets then either \(|x|\le |y|\) or \(|y|\le |x|\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

58

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\neq\aleph_{\alpha +1}\). (\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}})\) is Hartogs' aleph, the least \(\aleph\) not \(\le 2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\).)
Mathias [1979], p 126.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

59-le

If \((A,\le)\) is a partial ordering that is not a well ordering, then there is no set \(B\) such that \((B,\le)\) (the usual injective cardinal ordering on \(B\)) is isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).
Mathias [1979], p 120.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

63

\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
Jech [1973b], p 172 prob 8.5.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

65

The Krein-Milman Theorem: Let \(K\) be a compact convex set in a locally convex topological vector space \(X\). Then \(K\) has an extreme point. (An extreme point is a point which is not an interior point of any line segment which lies in  \(K\).) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985] p. 177.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

68

Nielsen-Schreier Theorem: Every subgroup of a free group is free.  Jech [1973b], p 12.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

69

Every field has an algebraic closure.  Jech [1973b], p 13.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

71-alpha
 

\(W_{\aleph_{\alpha}}\): \((\forall x)(|x|\le\aleph_{\alpha }\) or \(|x|\ge \aleph_{\alpha})\). Jech [1973b], page 119.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

72

Artin-Schreier Theorem:  Every field in which \(-1\) is not the sum of squares can be ordered. (The ordering, \(\le \), must satisfy (a) \(a\le b\rightarrow a + c\le b + c\) for all \(c\) and (b) \(c\ge 0\) and \(a\le b\rightarrow a\cdot c\le b\cdot c\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

73

\(\forall n\in\omega\), \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  For every \(n\in\omega\), if \(C\) is an infinite family of \(n\) element sets, then \(C\) has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

74

For every \(A\subseteq\Bbb R\) the following are equivalent:

  1. \(A\) is closed and bounded.
  2. Every sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subseteq A\) has a convergent subsequence with limit in A.
Jech [1973b], p 21.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

75

If a set has at least two elements, then it can be partitioned into well orderable subsets, each of which has at least two elements.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

77

A linear ordering of a set \(P\) is a well ordering if and only if \(P\) has no infinite descending sequences. Jech [1973b], p 23.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

78

Urysohn's Lemma:  If \(A\) and \(B\) are disjoint closed sets in a normal space \(S\), then there is a continuous \(f:S\rightarrow [0,1]\) which is 1 everywhere in \(A\) and 0 everywhere in \(B\). Urysohn [1925], pp 290-292.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

81-n

(For \(n\in\omega\)) \(K(n)\): For every set \(S\) there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a one to one function \(f: S \rightarrow {\cal P}^{n}(\alpha)\). (\({\cal P}^{0}(X) = X\) and \({\cal P}^{n+1}(X) = {\cal P}({\cal P}^{n}(X))\). (\(K(0)\) is equivalent to [1 AC]  and \(K(1)\) is equivalent to the selection principle (Form 15)).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

83

\(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

84

\(E(II,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): \((\forall x)(x\) is \(T\)-finite  if and only if \(\cal P(x)\) is Dedekind finite).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

86-alpha

\(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

87-alpha

\(DC(\aleph_{\alpha})\): Given a relation \(R\) such that for every subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\), there is an \(x\in X\) with \(Y\mathrel R x\) then there is a function \(f:\aleph_{\alpha}\to X\) such that (\(\forall\beta < \aleph_{\alpha}\)) \(\{f(\gamma): \gamma < \beta\}\mathrel R f(\beta)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

89

Antichain Principle:  Every partially ordered set has a maximal antichain. Jech [1973b], p 133.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

92

\(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

95-F

Existence of Complementary Subspaces over a Field \(F\): If \(F\) is a field, then every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that if \(S\subseteq V\) is a subspace of \(V\), then there is a subspace \(S'\subseteq V\) such that \(S\cap S'= \{0\}\) and \(S\cup S'\) generates \(V\). H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], pp 119ff, and Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.4.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

96

Löwig's Theorem:If \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are both bases for the vector space \(V\) then \(|B_{1}| = |B_{2}|\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

97

Cardinal Representatives: For every set \(A\) there is a function \(c\) with domain \({\cal P}(A)\) such that for all \(x, y\in {\cal P}(A)\), (i) \(c(x) = c(y) \leftrightarrow x\approx y\) and (ii) \(c(x)\approx x\).  Jech [1973b] p 154.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

98

The set of all finite subsets of a Dedekind finite set is Dedekind finite. Jech [1973b] p 161 prob 11.5.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

99

Rado's Selection Lemma: Let \(\{K(\lambda): \lambda \in\Lambda\}\) be a family  of finite subsets (of \(X\)) and suppose for each finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a function \(\gamma(S): S \rightarrow X\) such that \((\forall\lambda\in S)(\gamma(S)(\lambda)\in K(\lambda))\).  Then there is an \(f: \Lambda\rightarrow X\) such that for every finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a finite \(T\) such that \(S\subseteq T\subseteq\Lambda\) and such that \(f\) and \(\gamma (T)\) agree on S.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

102

For all Dedekind finite cardinals \(p\) and \(q\), if \(p^{2} = q^{2}\) then \(p = q\). Jech [1973b], p 162 prob 11.12.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

103

If \((P,<)\) is a linear ordering and \(|P| > \aleph_{1}\) then some initial segment of \(P\) is uncountable. Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.21.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

104

There is a regular uncountable aleph. Jech [1966b], p 165 prob 11.26.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

105

There is a  partially ordered set \((A,\le)\) such that for no set \(B\) is \((B,\le)\) (the ordering  on \(B\) is the usual injective cardinal ordering) isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

108

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\) is not the union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

109

Every field \(F\) and every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that each linearly independent set \(A\subseteq V\) can be extended to a basis. H.Rubin/J.~Rubin [1985], pp 119ff.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

111

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

112

\(MC(\infty,LO)\): For every family \(X\) of non-empty sets each of which can be linearly ordered there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

113

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many Spaces: The product of a countable set of compact spaces is compact.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

114

Every A-bounded \(T_2\) topological space is weakly Loeb. (\(A\)-bounded means amorphous subsets are relatively compact. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

115

The product of weakly Loeb \(T_2\) spaces is weakly Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

116

Every compact \(T_2\) space is weakly  Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

117

If \(\kappa\) is a measurable cardinal, then \(\kappa\) is the \(\kappa\)th inaccessible cardinal.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

118

Every linearly orderable topological space is normal.  Birkhoff [1967], p 241.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

119

van Douwen's choice principle: \(C(\aleph_{0}\),uniformly orderable with order type of the integers): Suppose \(\{ A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) is a set and there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(i\in\omega,\ f(i)\) is an ordering of \(A_{i}\) of type \(\omega^{*}+\omega\) (the usual ordering of the integers), then \(\{A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

120-K

If \(K\subseteq\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,K)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty sets each of whose cardinality is in \(K\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

123

\(SPI^*\): Uniform weak ultrafilter principle: For each family \(F\) of infinite sets \(\exists f\) such that \(\forall x\in F\), \(f(x)\) is a non-principal ultrafilter on \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

124

Every operator on a Hilbert space with an amorphous base is the direct sum of a finite matrix and  a  scalar operator.  (A set is amorphous if it is not the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

125

There does not exist an infinite, compact connected \(p\) space. (A \(p\) space is a \(T_2\) space in which the intersection of any well orderable family of open sets is open.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

127

An amorphous power of a compact \(T_2\) space, which as a set is well orderable, is well orderable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

128

Aczel's Realization Principle: On every infinite set there is a Hausdorff topology with an infinite set of non-isolated points.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

129

For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) admits a partition into sets of order type \(\omega^{*} + \omega\). (For every infinite \(A\), there is a set \(\{\langle C_j,<_j \rangle: j\in J\}\) such that \(\{C_j: j\in J\}\) is a partition of \(A\) and for each \(j\in J\), \(<_j\) is an ordering of \(C_j\) of type \(\omega^* + \omega\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

130

\({\cal P}(\Bbb R)\) is well orderable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

131

\(MC_\omega(\aleph_0,\infty)\): For every denumerable family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

134

If \(X\) is an infinite \(T_1\) space and \(X^{Y}\) is \(T_5\), then \(Y\) is countable. (\(T_5\) is 'hereditarily \(T_4\)'.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

135

If \(X\) is a \(T_2\) space with at least two points and \(X^{Y}\) is hereditarily metacompact then \(Y\) is  countable. (A space is metacompact if every open cover has an open point finite refinement. If \(B\) and \(B'\) are covers of a space \(X\), then \(B'\) is a refinement of \(B\) if \((\forall x\in B')(\exists y\in B)(x\subseteq y)\). \(B\) is point finite if \((\forall t\in X)\) there are only finitely many \(x\in B\) such that \(t\in x\).) van Douwen [1980]

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

136-k

Surjective Cardinal Cancellation (depends on \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\)): For all cardinals \(x\) and \(y\), \(kx\le^* ky\) implies \(x\le^* y\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

137-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\). If \(f\) is a 1-1 map from \(k\times X\) into \(k\times Y\) then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i} \) and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i} \) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  X_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  Y_{i})\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

138-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega\).  If \(f\) is a partial map from \(k\times Y\)  onto \(k\times X\) (that is, the domain is a subset of \(k\times Y\)), then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i}\)  and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i}\) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times Y_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup^{}_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times X_{i})\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

139

Using the discrete topology on 2, \(2^{\cal P(\omega)}\) is compact.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

140

Let \(\Omega\) be the set of all (undirected) infinite cycles of reals (Graphs whose vertices are real numbers, connected, no loops and each vertex adjacent to  exactly two others). Then there is a function \(f\) on \(\Omega \) such that for all \(s\in\Omega\), \(f(s)\) is a direction along \(s\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

141

[14 P(\(n\))] with \(n = 2\):  Let \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\) be a collection of sets such that \(\forall i\in I,\ |A(i)|\le 2\) and suppose \(R\) is a symmetric binary relation on \(\bigcup^{}_{i\in I} A(i)\) such that for all finite \(W\subseteq I\) there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i \in W\}\). Then there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

143

\(H(C,TR)\): If \((X,R)\) is a connected relation (\(u\neq v\rightarrow u\mathrel R v\) or \(v\mathrel R u\)) then \(X\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

144

Every set is almost well orderable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

145

Compact \(P_0\)-spaces are Dedekind finite. (A \(P_0\)-space is a topological space in which the intersection of a countable collection of open sets is open.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

146

\(A(F,A1)\): For every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\), if \(X\) is a continuous finite to one image of an A1 space then \((X,T)\) is  an A1 space. (\((X,T)\) is A1 means if \(U \subseteq  T\) covers \(X\) then \(\exists f : X\rightarrow U\) such that \((\forall x\in X) (x\in f(x)).)\)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

147

\(A(D2)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\) can be covered by a well ordered family of discrete sets.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

148

\(A(W2,B1)\): For every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\), if \(X\) is well ordered, then \(X\) has a well ordered base.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

149

\(A(F)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space is a continuous, finite to one image of an \(A1\) space.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

150

\(PC(\infty,\aleph_0,\infty)\): Every infinite set of denumerable sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

151

\(UT(WO,\aleph_{0},WO)\) (\(U_{\aleph_{1}}\)): The union of a well ordered set of denumerable sets is well  orderable. (If \(\kappa\) is a well ordered cardinal, see note 27 for \(UT(WO,\kappa,WO)\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

152

\(D_{\aleph_{0}}\): Every non-well-orderable set is the union of a pairwise disjoint, well orderable family of denumerable sets.  (See note 27 for \(D_{\kappa}\), \(\kappa\) a well ordered cardinal.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

153

The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact in the weak topology.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

154

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many \(T_2\) Spaces: The product of countably many \(T_2\) compact spaces is compact.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

155
 \(LC\): There are no non-trivial Läuchli continua. (A Läuchli continuum is a strongly connected continuum. Continuum \(\equiv\) compact, connected, Hausdorff space; and strongly connected \(\equiv\) every continuous real valued function is constant.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

156

Theorem of Gelfand and Kolmogoroff: Two compact \(T_2\) spaces are  homeomorphic if their rings of real valued continuous functions are isomorphic.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

157

Theorem of Goodner: A compact \(T_{2}\) space is extremally disconnected (the closure of every open set is open) if and only if each non-empty subset of \(C(X)\) (set of continuous real valued functions on \(X\)) which is pointwise bounded has a supremum.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

158

In every Hilbert space \(H\), if the closed unit ball is sequentially compact, then \(H\) has an orthonormal basis.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

159

The regular cardinals are cofinal in the class of ordinals.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

160

No Dedekind finite set can be mapped onto an aleph. (See [9 E].)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

161

Definability of cardinal addition in terms of \(\le\): There is a first order formula whose only non-logical symbol is \( \le \) (for cardinals) that defines cardinal addition.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

162

Non-existence of infinite units: There is no infinite cardinal number \(A\) such that \(A + A > A\)  and for all cardinals \(x\) and \(y\), \(x + y = A\rightarrow x = A\) or \(y = A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

163

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite, Dedekind finite subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

164

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite subset with a Dedekind finite power set.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

166

\(PC(\infty,2,\infty)\): Every infinite family of pairs has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

167

\(PKW(\aleph_{0},\ge 2,\infty)\), Partial Kinna-Wagner Principle:  For every denumerable family \(F\) such that for all \(x\in F\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is an infinite subset \(H\subseteq F\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in H\), \(\emptyset\neq f(x) \subsetneq x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

168

Dual Cantor-Bernstein Theorem:\((\forall x) (\forall y)(|x| \le^*|y|\) and \(|y|\le^* |x|\) implies  \(|x| = |y|)\) .

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

169

There is an uncountable subset of \({\Bbb R}\) without a perfect subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

170

\(\aleph_{1}\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

171

If \((P,\le)\) is a partial order such that \(P\) is the denumerable union of finite sets and all antichains in \(P\) are finite then for each denumerable family \({\cal D}\) of dense sets there is a \({\cal D}\) generic filter.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

172

For every infinite set \(S\), if \(S\) is hereditarily countable  (that is, every \(y\in TC(S)\) is countable) then \(|TC(S)|= \aleph_{0}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

173

\(MPL\): Metric spaces are para-Lindelöf.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

174-alpha

\(RM1,\aleph_{\alpha }\): The representation theorem for multi-algebras with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations:  Assume \((A,F)\) is  a  multi-algebra  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations (and no other operations). Then  there  is  an  algebra \((B,G)\)  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations and an equivalence relation \(E\) on \(B\) such that \((B/E,G/E)\) and \((A,F)\) are isomorphic multi-algebras.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

175

Transitivity Condition: For all sets \(x\), there is a set \(u\) and a function \(f\) such that \(u\) is transitive and \(f\) is a one to one function from \(x\) onto \(u\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

176

Every infinite, locally finite group has an infinite Abelian subgroup. (Locally finite means every finite subset generates a finite subgroup.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

177

An infinite box product of regular \(T_1\) spaces, each of cardinality greater than 1, is neither first countable nor connected.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

178-n-N

If  \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\) and \(N \subseteq \{ 1, 2, \ldots , n-1 \}\), \(N \neq\emptyset\), \(MC(\infty,n, N)\):  If \(X\) is any set of \(n\)-element sets then  there is  a function \(f\) with domain \(X\) such that for all \(A\in X\), \(f(A)\subseteq A\) and \(|f(A)|\in N\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

179-epsilon

Suppose  \(\epsilon > 0\) is an ordinal. \(\forall x\), \(x\in W(\epsilon\)).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

180

Every Abelian group has a divisible hull.  (If \(A\) and \(B\)  are groups, \(B\) is a divisible hull of \(A\) means \(B\) is a divisible group, \(A\) is a subgroup of \(B\) and for every non-zero \(b \in  B\), \(\exists  n \in \omega \)  such that \(0\neq nb\in A\).)  Fuchs [1970], Theorem 24.4 p 107.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

181

\(C(2^{\aleph_0},\infty)\): Every set \(X\) of non-empty sets such that \(|X|=2^{\aleph_0}\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

182

There is an aleph whose cofinality is greater than \(\aleph_{0}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

183-alpha

There are no \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) minimal  sets.  That is, there are no sets \(X\) such that

  1. \(|X|\) is incomparable with \(\aleph_{\alpha}\)
  2. \(\aleph_{\beta}<|X|\) for every \(\beta < \alpha \) and
  3. \(\forall Y\subseteq X, |Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\) or \(|X-Y| <\aleph_{\alpha}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

184

Existence of a double uniformization: For all \(X\) and \(Y\), for all \(E\subseteq X\times Y\), if there is an infinite cardinal \(\kappa\) satisfying:

  1. \(\forall y_0\in Y\), \(|\{(x,y_0): x\in X\}\cap E| =\kappa\) and
  2. \(\forall x_0\in X\), \(|\{(x_0,y): y\in Y\}\cap E| = \kappa\),
then \(\exists U\subseteq E\) such that for all \((x,y)\in E, \exists !z\in X\) such that \((z,y)\in U\) and \(\exists !z\in Y\) such that \((x,z)\in U\). (\(U\) is called a double uniformization of \(E\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

185

Every linearly ordered Dedekind finite set is finite.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

186

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a least upper bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

187

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a greatest lower bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

188

\(EP\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is a projective Abelian group \(G\) and a homomorphism from \(G\) onto \(A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

189

\(EI\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is an injective Abelian group \(G\) and a one to one homomorphism from \(A\) into \(G\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

190

There is a non-trivial injective Abelian group.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

191

\(SVC\): There is a set \(S\) such that for every set \(a\), there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a function from \(S\times\alpha\) onto \(a\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

192

\(EP\) sets: For every set \(A\) there is a projective set \(X\) and a function from \(X\) onto \(A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

193

\(EFP\ Ab\): Every Abelian group is a homomorphic image of a free projective Abelian group.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

194

\(C(\varPi^1_2)\) or \(AC(\varPi^1_2)\): If \(P\in \omega\times{}^{\omega}\omega\), \(P\) has domain \(\omega\), and \(P\) is in \(\varPi^1_2\), then there is a sequence of elements \(\langle x_{k}: k\in\omega\rangle\) of \({}^{\omega}\omega\) with \(\langle k,x_{k}\rangle \in P\) for all \(k\in\omega\). Kanovei [1979].

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

195

Every general linear system has a linear global reaction.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

196-alpha

\(\aleph_{\alpha}\) and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) are not both measurable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

197

\({\Bbb R}^{2}\) is the union of three sets \(C\) with the property that for all \(x\in C\) there is a straight line \(L\) such that \(L\cap C = \{x\}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

198

For every set \(S\), if the only linearly orderable subsets of \(S\) are the finite subsets of \(S\), then either \(S\) is finite or \(S\) has an amorphous subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

199(\(n\))

(For \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\)) If all \(\varSigma^{1}_{n}\), Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega }\omega\) are finite, then all \(\varPi^1_n\) Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega} \omega\) are finite.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

200

For all infinite \(x\), \(|2^{x}| = |x!|\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

201

Linking Axiom for Boolean Algebras: Every Boolean algebra has a maximal linked system. (\(L\subseteq B\) is linked if \(a\wedge b\neq 0\) for all \(a\) and \(b \in L\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

204

For every infinite \(X\), there is a function from \(X\) onto \(2X\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

205

For all cardinals \(m\) and \(n\), if \(m\le^* n\) and \(\neg (n\le^* m)\) then there is a cardinal \(k \le n\) such that \(m\le^* k\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

206

The existence of a non-principal ultrafilter: There exists an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal ultrafilter on \(X\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

207-alpha

\(UT(\aleph_{\alpha },\aleph_{\alpha}, <2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\): The union of \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) sets each of cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) has cardinality less than \(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

208

For all ordinals \(\alpha\), \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\le 2^{\aleph_\alpha}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

209

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that for all \(X\), if \(X\) is a denumerable union of denumerable sets then \({\cal P}(X)\) cannot be partitioned into \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) non-empty sets.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

210

The commutator subgroup of a free group is free.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

212

\(C(2^{\aleph_{0}},\subseteq{\Bbb R})\): If \(R\) is a relation on \({\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), there is a \(y\in{\Bbb R}\) such that \(x\mathrel R y\), then there is a function \(f: {\Bbb R} \rightarrow{\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), \(x\mathrel R f(x)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

213

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{1})\): If \((\forall y\in X)(|y| = \aleph_{1})\) then \(X\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

214

\(Z(\omega)\): For every family \(A\) of infinite sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in A\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty subset of \(y\) and \(|f(y)|=\aleph_{0}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

215

If \((\forall y\subseteq X)(y\) can be linearly ordered implies \(y\) is finite), then \(X\) is finite.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

216

Every infinite tree has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

217

Every infinite partially ordered set has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

219

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0\}) MC(\infty,WO\), relatively prime to \(n\)): For all non-zero \(n\in \omega\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty well orderable sets, then there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\), and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

220-p

Suppose \(p\in\omega\) and \(p\) is a prime. Any two elementary Abelian \(p\)-groups (all non-trivial elements have order \(p\)) of the same cardinality are isomorphic.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

221

For all infinite \(X\), there is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

223

There is an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

224

There is a partition of the real line into \(\aleph_1\) Borel sets \(\{B_\alpha: \alpha<\aleph_1\}\) such that for some \(\beta <\aleph_1\), \(\forall\alpha <\aleph_1\), \(B_{\alpha}\in G_{\beta}\). (\(G_\beta\) for \(\beta < \aleph_1\) is defined by induction, \(G_0=\{A: A\) is an open subset of \({\Bbb R}\}\) and for \(\beta > 0\),

  • \(G_\beta =\left\{\bigcup^\infty_{i=0}A_{i}: (\forall i\in\omega) (\exists\xi <\beta)(A_i\in G_\xi)\,\right\}\) if \(\beta\) is even and
  • \(G_\beta = \left\{\bigcap^\infty_{i=0}A_{i}: (\forall i\in\omega) (\exists \xi < \beta)(A_{i}\in G_\xi)\,\right\}\) if \(\beta\) is odd.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

225

Every proper filter on \(\omega\) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

226

Let \(R\) be a commutative ring with identity, \(B\) a proper subring containing 1 and \(q\) a prime ideal in \(B\). Then there is a subring \(A\) of \(R\) and a prime ideal \(p\) in \(A\) such that

  1. \(B\subseteq A\)
  2. \(q = B\cap p\)
  3. \(R - p\) is multiplicatively closed and
  4. if \(A\neq R\),
then \(R - A\) is multiplicatively closed.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

227

For all groups \(G\), if every finite subgroup of \(G\) can be fully ordered then \(G\) can be fully ordered.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

228

Every torsion free Abelian group can be fully ordered.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

229

If \((G,\circ,\le)\) is a partially ordered group, then \(\le\) can be extended to a linear order on \(G\) if and only if for every finite set \(\{a_{1},\ldots, a_{n}\}\subseteq G\), with \(a_{i}\neq\) the identity for \(i = 1\) to \(n\), the signs \(\epsilon_{1}, \ldots,\epsilon_{n}\) (\(\epsilon_{i} = \pm 1\)) can be chosen so that \(P\cap S(a^{\epsilon_{1}}_{1},\ldots,a^{\epsilon_{n}}_{n})=\emptyset\) (where \(S(b_{1},\ldots,b_{n})\) is the normal sub-semi-group of \(G\) generated by \(b_{1},\ldots, b_{n}\) and \(P = \{g\in G: e\le g\}\) where \(e\) is the identity of \(G\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

230

\(L^{1} = HOD\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

232

Every metric space \((X,d)\) has a \(\sigma\)-point finite base.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

233

Artin-Schreier theorem: If a field has an algebraic closure it is unique up to isomorphism.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

234

There is a non-Ramsey set: There is a set \(A\) of infinite subsets of \(\omega\) such that for every infinite subset \(N\) of \(\omega\), \(N\) has a subset which is in \(A\) and a subset which is not in \(A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

235

If \(V\) is a vector space and \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are bases for \(V\) then \(|B_{1}|\) and \(|B_{2}|\) are comparable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

236

If \(V\) is a vector space with a basis and \(S\) is a linearly independent subset of \(V\) such that no proper extension of \(S\) is a basis for \(V\), then \(S\) is a basis for \(V\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

237

The order of any group is divisible by the order of any of its subgroups, (i.e., if \(H\) is a subgroup of \(G\) then there is a set \(A\) such that \(|H\times A| = |G|\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

238

Every elementary Abelian group (that is, for some prime \(p\) every non identity element has order \(p\)) is the direct sum of cyclic subgroups.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

239

AL20(\(\mathbb Q\)):  Every vector \(V\) space over \(\mathbb Q\) has the property that every linearly independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis. Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p.119, AL20.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

240

If a group \(G\) satisfies "every ascending chain of subgroups is finite", then every subgroup of \(G\) is finitely generated.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

241

Every algebraic closure of \(\Bbb Q\) has a real closed subfield.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

242

There is, up to an isomorphism, at most one algebraic closure of \({\Bbb Q}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

243

Every  principal ideal domain is a unique factorization domain.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

244

Every principal ideal domain has a maximal ideal.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

245

There is a function \(f :\omega_1\rightarrow \omega^{\omega}_1\) such that for every \(\alpha\), \(0 < \alpha < \omega_1\), \(f(\alpha )\) is a function from \(\omega\) onto \(\alpha\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

246

The monadic theory theory \(MT(\omega_1,<)\) of \(\omega_1\) is recursive.  \ac{Litman} \cite{1976} and note 85.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

247

Every atomless Boolean algebra is Dedekind infinite.  \ac{Plotkin} \cite{1976}, notes 86 and 94.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

248

For any \(\kappa\), \(\kappa\) is the cardinal number of an infinite complete Boolean algebra if and only if \(\kappa^{\aleph_0} = \kappa \).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

249

If \(T\) is an infinite tree in which every element has exactly 2 immediate successors then \(T\) has an infinite branch.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

251

The additive groups \(({\Bbb R},+)\) and \(({\Bbb C},+)\) are  isomorphic.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

252

The additive groups of \(\Bbb Q\oplus\Bbb R\) and \(\Bbb R\) are isomorphic.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

253

\L o\'s' Theorem: If \(M=\langle A,R_j\rangle_{j\in J}\) is a relational system, \(X\) any set and \({\cal F}\) an ultrafilter in \({\cal P}(X)\), then \(M\) and \(M^{X}/{\cal F}\) are elementarily equivalent.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

254

\(Z(D,R,l)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which ramified subsets have least upper bounds, has a maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

255

\(Z(D,R)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

256

\(Z(P,F)\): Every partially ordered set \((X,R)\) in which every forest \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

257

\(Z(TR,P)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which  every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

258

\(Z(D,L)\): Every directed relation \((X,R)\) in which linearly ordered subsets have upper bounds, has a maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

259

\(Z(TR\&C,W)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every well ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

260

\(Z(TR\&C,P)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

261

\(Z(TR,T)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every subset which is a tree has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

262

\(Z(TR,R)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

263

\(H(AS\&C,P)\): Every every relation \((X,R)\) which is antisymmetric and connected contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

264

\(H(C,P)\): Every connected relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered set.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

265

\(H(A,TR)\): Every relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

266

\(H(AS,P)\): Every antisymmetric relation contains \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

267

There is no infinite, free complete Boolean algebra.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

268

If \({\cal L}\)  is  a  lattice  isomorphic  to the  lattice  of subalgebras of some unary universal algebra (a unary universal algebra is one with only unary or nullary operations) and \(\alpha \) is an automorphism of \({\cal L}\) of order 2 (that is, \(\alpha ^{2}\)  is  the  identity) then there is a unary algebra \(\frak A\)  and an isomorphism \(\rho \) from \({\cal L}\) onto the lattice of subalgebras of \(\frak A^{2}\) with \[\rho(\alpha(x))=(\rho(x))^{-1} (= \{(s,t) : (t,s)\in\rho(x)\})\] for all \(x\in  {\cal L}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

269

For every cardinal \(m\), there is a set \(A\) such that \(2^{|A|^2}\ge m\) and there is a choice function on the collection of 2-element subsets of \(A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

270

\(CT_{\hbox{fin}}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs only in a finite number of formulas.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

271-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(CT_{n}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs in at most \(n\) formulas.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

272

There is an \(X\subseteq{\Bbb R}\) such that neither \(X\) nor \(\Bbb R - X\) has a perfect subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

273

There is a subset of \({\Bbb R}\) which is not Borel.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

274

There is a cardinal number \(x\) and an \(n\in\omega\) such that \(\neg(x\) adj\(^n\, x^2)\). (The expression ``\(x\) adj\(^n\, ya\)" means there are cardinals \(z_0,\ldots, z_n\) such that \(z_0 = x\) and \(z_n = y\) and for all \(i,\ 0\le i < n,\ z_i< z_{i+1}\) and if  \(z_i < z\le z_{i+1}\), then \(z = z_{i+1}.)\) (Compare with [0 A]).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

275

The sequence of cardinals \(\langle\aleph_n: n \in\omega\rangle\) has a unique minimal upper bound.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

276

\(E(V'',III)\): For every set \(A\), \({\cal P}(A)\) is Dedekind finite if and only if \(A = \emptyset\)  or \(2|{\cal P}(A)| > |{\cal P}(A)|\). \ac{Howard/Spi\u siak} \cite{1994}.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

277

\(E(D,VII)\): Every non-well-orderable cardinal is decomposable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

278

In an integral domain \(R\), if every ideal is finitely generated then \(R\) has a maximal proper ideal. note 45 E.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

279

The Closed Graph Theorem for operations between Fréchet Spaces: Suppose \(X\) and \(Y\) are Fréchet spaces, \(T:X\to Y\) is linear and \(G=\{(x,Tx): x \in X \}\) is closed in \(X\times Y\). Then \(T\) is continuous. Rudin [1991] p. 51.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

280

There is a complete separable metric space with a subset which does not have the Baire property.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

281

There is a Hilbert space \(H\) and an  unbounded linear operator on \(H\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

282

\(\omega\not\to(\omega)^{\omega}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

283

Cardinality of well ordered subsets:  For all \(n\in\omega\) and for all infinite \(x\), \(|x^n| < |s(x)|\) where \(s(x)\) is the set of all well orderable subsets of \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

284

A system of linear equations over a field \(F\) has a solution in \(F\) if and only if every finite sub-system has a solution in \(F\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

285

Let \(E\) be a set and \(f: E\to E\), then \(f\) has a fixed point if and only if \(E\) is not the union of three mutually disjoint sets \(E_1\), \(E_2\) and \(E_3\) such that \(E_i \cap f(E_i) = \emptyset\) for \(i=1, 2, 3\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

286

Extended Krein-Milman Theorem:  Let K be a quasicompact (sometimes called convex-compact), convex subset of a locally convex topological vector space, then K has an extreme point. H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], p. 177-178.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

287

The Hahn-Banach Theorem for Separable Normed Linear Spaces:  Assume \(V\) is a separable normed linear space and \(p :V \to \Bbb R\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t \ge 0)(\forall x \in V)(p(tx) = tp(x))\) and assume \(f\) is a linear function from a subspace \(S\) of \(V\) into \(\Bbb R\) which satisfies \((\forall x \in S)(f(x) \le p(x))\), then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^* :V \to \Bbb R\) so that \(f^* \) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^*(x) \le p(x))\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

289

If \(S\) is a set of subsets of a countable set and \(S\) is closed under chain unions, then \(S\) has a \(\subseteq\)-maximal element.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

290

For all infinite \(x\), \(|2^x|=|x^x|\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

291

For all infinite \(x\), \(|x!|=|x^x|\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

292

\(MC(LO,\infty)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

293

For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\) can be linearly ordered and there is a mapping of \(x\) onto \(y\), then \(y\) can be linearly ordered.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

294

Every linearly ordered \(W\)-set is well orderable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

295

DO:  Every infinite set has a dense linear ordering.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

296

Part-\(\infty\): Every infinite set is the disjoint union of infinitely many infinite sets.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

297

Extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces are projective in the category of all compact Hausdorff spaces.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

298

Every compact Hausdorff space has a Gleason cover.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

299

Any extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff space is projective in the category of Boolean topological spaces.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

300

Any continuous surjection between extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

301

Any continuous surjection between Boolean spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

302

Any continuous surjection between compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

303

If \(B\) is a Boolean algebra, \(S\subseteq B\) and \(S\) is closed under \(\land\), then there is a \(\subseteq\)-maximal proper ideal \(I\) of \(B\) such that \(I\cap S= \{0\}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

304

There does not exist a \(T_2\) topological space \(X\) such that every infinite subset of \(X\) contains an infinite compact subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

305

There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Vitali equivalence classes. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).). \ac{Kanovei} \cite{1991}.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

306

The set of Vitali equivalence classes is linearly orderable. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow (\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y = q)\).).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

307

If \(m\) is the cardinality of the set of Vitali equivalence classes, then \(H(m) = H(2^{\aleph_0})\), where \(H\) is Hartogs aleph function and the {\it Vitali equivalence classes} are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in {\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

308-p

If \(p\) is a prime and if \(\{G_y: y\in Y\}\) is a set of finite groups, then the weak direct product \(\prod_{y\in Y}G_y\) has a maximal \(p\)-subgroup.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

309

The Banach-Tarski Paradox: There are three finite partitions \(\{P_1,\ldots\), \(P_n\}\), \(\{Q_1,\ldots,Q_r\}\) and \(\{S_1,\ldots,S_n, T_1,\ldots,T_r\}\) of \(B^3 = \{x\in {\Bbb R}^3 : |x| \le 1\}\) such that \(P_i\) is congruent to \(S_i\) for \(1\le i\le n\) and \(Q_i\) is congruent to \(T_i\) for \(1\le i\le r\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

310

The Measure Extension Theorem: Suppose that \(\cal A_0\) is a subring (that is, \(a,b \in \cal A_0  \to a\vee b \in \cal A_0\) and \(a-b \in \cal A_0\)) of a Boolean algebra \(\cal A\) and \(\mu\) is a measure on \(\cal A_0\) (that is, \(\mu:\cal A \to [0,\infty]\), \(\mu(a\vee b) =\mu(a)+\mu(b)\) for \(a\land b = 0\), and \(\mu(0) = 0\).) then there is a measure on \(\cal A\) that extends \(\mu\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

311

Abelian groups are amenable. (\(G\) is amenable if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G)=1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

312

A subgroup of an amenable group is amenable. (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g \in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

313

\(\Bbb Z\) (the set of integers under addition) is amenable.  (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

314

For every set \(X\) and every permutation \(\pi\) on \(X\) there are two reflections \(\rho\) and \(\sigma\) on \(X\) such that \(\pi =\rho\circ\sigma\) and for every \(Y\subseteq X\) if \(\pi[Y]=Y\) then \(\rho[Y]=Y\) and \(\sigma[Y]=Y\).  (A reflection is a permutation \(\phi\) such that \(\phi^2\) is the identity.) \ac{Degen} \cite{1988}, \cite{2000}.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

315

\(\Omega = \omega_1\), where
\(\Omega = \{\alpha\in\hbox{ On}: (\forall\beta\le\alpha)(\beta=0 \vee (\exists\gamma)(\beta=\gamma+1) \vee\)
there is a sequence \(\langle\gamma_n: n\in\omega\rangle\) such that for each \(n\),
\(\gamma_n<\beta\hbox{ and } \beta=\bigcup_{n<\omega}\gamma_n.)\} \)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

316

If a linearly ordered set \((A,\le)\) has the fixed point property then \((A,\le)\) is complete. (\((A,\le)\)  has the fixed point property if every function \(f:A\to A\) satisfying \((x\le y \Rightarrow f(x)\le f(y))\) has a fixed point, and (\((A,\le)\) is complete if every subset of \(A\) has a least upper bound.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

317

Weak Sikorski Theorem:  If \(B\) is a complete, well orderable Boolean algebra and \(f\) is a homomorphism of the Boolean algebra \(A'\) into \(B\) where \(A'\) is a subalgebra of the Boolean algebra \(A\), then \(f\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

318

\(\aleph_1\) is not measurable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

319

Measurable cardinals are inaccessible.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

320

No successor cardinal, \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\), is measurable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

321

There does not exist an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) is weakly compact and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) is measurable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

325

Ramsey's Theorem II: \(\forall n,m\in\omega\), if A is an infinite set and the family of all \(m\) element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into \(n\) sets \(S_{j}, 1\le j\le n\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all \(m\) element subsets of \(B\) belong to the same \(S_{j}\). (Also, see Form 17.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

326

2-SAT:  Restricted Compactness Theorem for Propositional Logic III:   If \(\Sigma\) is a set of formulas in a propositional language such that every finite subset of \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable and if every formula in \(\Sigma\) is a disjunction of at most two literals, then \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable. (A literal is a propositional variable or its negation.) Wojtylak [1999] (listed as Wojtylak [1995])

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

327

\(KW(WO,<\aleph_0)\),  The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of finite sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

328

\(MC(WO,\infty)\): For  every well ordered set \(X\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that and for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\). (See Form 67.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

329

\(MC(\infty,WO)\): For  every set \(M\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

331

If \((X_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of compact non-empty topological spaces then there is a family \((F_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(F_i\) is an irreducible closed subset of \(X_i\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

332
 

A product of non-empty compact sober topological spaces is non-empty.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

333

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

334

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\hbox{ even})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is even.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

335-n

Every quotient group of an Abelian group each of whose elements has order  \(\le n\) has a set of representatives.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

337

\(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered):  If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

338

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,WO)\): The union of a denumerable number of denumerable sets is well orderable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

339

Martin's Axiom \((\aleph_{0})\): Whenever \((P\le)\) is a non-empty, ccc  quasi-order (ccc means every anti-chain is countable) and \({\cal D}\) is a family of \(\le\aleph_0\) dense subsets of \(P\), then there is a \({\cal D}\) generic filter \(G\) in \(P\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

340

Every Lindelöf metric space is separable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

341

Every Lindelöf metric space is second countable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

343

A product of non-empty, compact \(T_2\) topological spaces is non-empty.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

344

If \((E_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of non-empty sets, then there is a family \((U_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(U_i\) is an ultrafilter on \(E_i\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

345

Rasiowa-Sikorski Axiom:  If \((B,\land,\lor)\) is a Boolean algebra, \(a\) is a non-zero element of \(B\), and \(\{X_n: n\in\omega\}\) is a denumerable set of subsets of \(B\) then there is a maximal filter \(F\) of \(B\) such that \(a\in F\) and for each \(n\in\omega\), if \(X_n\subseteq F\) and \(\bigwedge X_n\) exists then \(\bigwedge X_n \in F\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

346

If \(V\) is a vector space without a finite basis then \(V\) contains an infinite, well ordered, linearly independent subset.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

347

Idemmultiple Partition Principle: If \(y\) is idemmultiple (\(2\times y\approx y\)) and \(x\precsim ^* y\), then \(x\precsim y\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

348

If \(G\) is a group and \(X\) and \(Y\) both freely generate \(G\) then \(|X| = |Y|\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

349

\(MC(\infty,\aleph_0)\): For every set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

351

A countable product of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

352

A countable product of second countable spaces is second countable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

353

A countable product of first countable spaces is first countable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

354

A countable product of separable \(T_2\) spaces is separable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

355

\(KW(\aleph_0,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

356

  \(KW(\infty,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of denumerable sets: For every set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

357

\(KW(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of denumerable sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

358

\(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

359

If \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| \le |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| \le |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

360

A system of linear equations over the field \(\{0,1\}\) has a solution, if and only if every finite subsystem has a solution. Brunner [2001]

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

361

In \(\Bbb R\), the union of a denumerable number of analytic sets is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

362

In \(\Bbb R\), every Borel set is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

363

There are exactly \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Borel sets in \(\Bbb R\). G. Moore [1982], p 325.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

364

In \(\Bbb R\), there is a measurable set that is not Borel.  G. Moore [1982], p 325.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

365

For every uncountable set \(A\), if \(A\) has the same cardinality as each of its uncountable subsets then \(|A| = \aleph_1\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

366

There is a discontinuous function \(f: \Bbb R \to\Bbb R\) such that for all real \(x\) and \(y\), \(f(x+y)=f(x)+f(y)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

367

There is a Hamel basis for \(\Bbb R\) as a vector space over \(\Bbb Q\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

368

The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

369

If \(\Bbb R\) is partitioned into two sets, at least one of them has cardinality \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

370

Weak Gelfand Extreme Point Theorem: If \(A\) is a non-trivial Gelfand algebra then the closed unit ball in the dual of \(A\) has an extreme point \(e\).  Morillon [1986].

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

371

There is an infinite, compact, Hausdorff, extremally disconnected topological space.  Morillon [1993].

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

372

Generalized Hahn-Banach Theorem:  Assume that \(X\) is a real vector space, \((Z,\preccurlyeq)\) is a Dedekind complete ordered vector space and \(X_0\) is a subspace of \(X\).  If \(\lambda_0 : X_0 \to Z\) is linear and \(p: X\to Z\) is sublinear and if \(\lambda_0 \preccurlyeq p\) on \(X_0\) then \(\lambda_0\) can be extended to a linear map \(\lambda : X\to Z\) such that \(\lambda \preccurlyeq p\) on \(X\). \ac{Schechter} \cite{1996b}

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

373-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\aleph_0,n,\infty)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

374-n

\(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

375

Tietze-Urysohn Extension Theorem: If \((X,T)\) is a normal topological space, \(A\) is closed in \(X\), and \(f: A\to [0,1]\) is continuous, then there exists a continuous function \(g: X\to [0,1]\) which extends \(f\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

376

Restricted Kinna Wagner Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for every \(z\subseteq Y\), if \(|z| \ge 2\) then \(f(z)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(z\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

377

Restricted Ordering Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that \(Y\) can be linearly ordered.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

378

Restricted Choice for Families of Well Ordered Sets:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that the family of non-empty well orderable subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

379

\(PKW(\infty,\infty,\infty)\): For every infinite family \(X\) of sets each of which has at least two elements, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in Y\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(y\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

380

\(PC(\infty,WO,\infty)\):  For every infinite family of non-empty well orderable sets, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) which has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

381

DUM:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

382

DUMN:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is normal.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

384

Closed Filter Extendability for \(T_1\) Spaces: Every closed filter in a \(T_1\) topological space can be extended to a maximal closed filter.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

385

Countable Ultrafilter Theorem:  Every proper filter with a countable base over a set \(S\) (in \({\cal P}(S)\)) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

386

Every B compact (pseudo)metric space is Baire.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

387

DPO:  Every infinite set has a non-trivial, dense partial order.  (A partial ordering \(<\) on a set \(X\) is dense if \((\forall x, y\in X)(x \lt y \to (\exists z \in X)(x \lt z \lt y))\) and is non-trivial if \((\exists x,y\in X)(x \lt y)\)).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

388

Every infinite branching poset (a partially ordered set in which each element has at least two lower bounds) has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

389

\(C(\aleph_0,2,\cal P({\Bbb R}))\): Every denumerable family of two element subsets of \(\cal P({\Bbb R})\) has a choice function.  \ac{Keremedis} \cite{1999b}.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

390

Every infinite set can be partitioned either into two infinite sets or infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

391

\(C(\infty,LO)\): Every set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

393

\(C(LO,WO)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty well orderable sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

394

\(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

395

\(MC(LO,LO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

396

\(MC(LO,WO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty well orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

397

\(MC(WO,LO)\): For each well ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

398

\(KW(LO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered family of sets: For every linearly ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

399

\(KW(\infty,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a set of linearly orderable sets: For every set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

401

\(KW(LO,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of finite sets: For every linearly ordered set of finite sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

402

\(KW(WO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every well ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

403

\(KW(LO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of well orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of well orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

404

Every infinite set can be partitioned into infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

405

Every infinite set can be partitioned into sets each of which is countable and has at least two elements.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

406

The product of compact Hausdorf spaces is countably compact. Alas [1994].

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

407

Let \(B\) be a Boolean algebra, \(b\) a non-zero element of \(B\) and \(\{A_i: i\in\omega\}\) a sequence of subsets of \(B\) such that for each \(i\in\omega\), \(A_i\) has a supremum \(a_i\). Then there exists an ultrafilter \(D\) in \(B\) such that \(b\in D\) and, for each \(i\in\omega\), if \(a_i\in D\), then \(D\cap\ A_i\neq\emptyset\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

409

Suppose \((G,\Gamma)\) is a locally finite graph (i.e. \(G\) is a non-empty set and \(\Gamma\) is a function from \(G\) to \(\cal P(G)\) such that for each \(x\in G\), \(\Gamma(x)\) and \(\Gamma^{-1}\{x\}\) are finite), \(K\) is a finite set of integers, and \(T\) is a function mapping subsets of \(K\) into subsets of \(K\). If for each finite subgraph \((A,\Gamma_A)\) there is a function \(\psi\) such that for each \(x\in A\), \(\psi(x)\in T(\psi[\Gamma_A(x)])\), then there is a function \(\phi\) such that for all \(x\in G\), \(\phi(x)\in T(\phi[\Gamma(x)])\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

410

RC (Reflexive Compactness): The closed unit ball of a reflexive normed space is compact for the weak topology.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

411

RCuc (Reflexive Compactness for uniformly convex Banach spaces): The closed unit ball of a uniformly convex Banach space is compact for the weak topology.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

412

RCh (Reflexive Compactness for Hilbert spaces): The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact for the weak topology.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

413

Every infinite set \(S\) is the union of a set, well-ordered by inclusion, of subsets which are non-equipollent to \(S\).  

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

414

Every \(\cal W\)-frame is a \(\cal D\)-frame.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

415

Every \(\cal W\)-compactly generated complete lattice is algebraic.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

416

Every non-compact topological space \(S\) is the union of a set that is well-ordered by inclusion and consists of open proper subsets of \(S\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

417

On every non-trivial Banach space there is a non-trivial linear functional (bounded or unbounded).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

418

DUM(\(\aleph_0\)): The countable disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

419

UT(\(\aleph_0\),cuf,cuf): The union of a denumerable set of cuf sets is cuf. (A set is cuf if it is a countable union of finite sets.)

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

420

\(UT(\aleph_0\),\(\aleph_0\),cuf): The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is cuf.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

421
  \(UT(\aleph_0,WO,WO)\): The union of a denumerable set of well orderable sets can be well ordered.
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

422-n

\(UT(WO,n,WO)\), \(n\in \omega-\{0,1\}\): The union of a well ordered set of \(n\) element sets can be well ordered.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

424
 Every Lindel\"{o}f metric space is super second countable.  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159. \iput{super second countable}
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

425
 For every first countable topological space \((X, \Cal T)\) there is a family \((\Cal D(x))_{x \in X}\) such that \(\forall x \in X\), \(D(x)\) countable local base at \(x\).  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159.
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

426

If \((X,\cal T) \) is a first countable topological space and \((\cal B(x))_{x\in X}\) is a family such that for all \(x \in X\), \(\cal B(x)\) is a local base at \(x\), then there is a family \(( \cal V(x))_{x\in X}\) such that for every \(x \in X\), \(\cal V(x)\) is a countable local base at \(x\) and \(\cal V(x) \subseteq \cal B(x)\).

1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

427
\(\exists F\) AL20(\(F\)): There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that every independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis.  \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, AL20}.
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

428
\(\exists F\) B\((F)\):  There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space over \(F\) has a basis. \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

429-p
(Where \(p\) is a prime) B: Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
1

\(C(\infty,\infty)\):  The Axiom of Choice: Every  set  of  non-empty sets has a choice function.

430-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) \(AL21\)\((p)\): Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that for every subspace \(S\) of \(V\), there is a subspace \(S'\) of \(V\) such that \(S \cap S' = \{ 0 \}\) and \(S \cup S'\) generates \(V\) in other words such that \(V = S \oplus S'\).   Rubin, H./Rubin, J [1985], p.119, AL21.

2

Existence of successor cardinals: For every cardinal \(m\) there is a cardinal \(n\) such that \(m < n\) and \((\forall p < n)(p \le m)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
3
 \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
0
 \(0 = 0\).
4

Every infinite set is the union of some disjoint family of denumerable subsets. (Denumerable means \(\cong \aleph_0\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
6

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): The union of a denumerable  family  of denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is denumerable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
7

There is no infinite decreasing sequence of cardinals.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
8

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\):

0
 \(0 = 0\).
9

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

10

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

11

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) has an infinite subset \(B\) such that for every \(n\in\omega\), \(n>0\), the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

0
 \(0 = 0\).
11

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) has an infinite subset \(B\) such that for every \(n\in\omega\), \(n>0\), the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

11

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) has an infinite subset \(B\) such that for every \(n\in\omega\), \(n>0\), the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

12

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\) and every \(n\in\omega\), there is an infinite subset \(B\) of \(A\) such the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco} [1998b]

0
 \(0 = 0\).
12

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\) and every \(n\in\omega\), there is an infinite subset \(B\) of \(A\) such the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco} [1998b]

12

A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\) and every \(n\in\omega\), there is an infinite subset \(B\) of \(A\) such the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco} [1998b]

13

Every Dedekind finite subset of \({\Bbb R}\) is finite.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

14

BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal.

15

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

0
 \(0 = 0\).
16

\(C(\aleph_{0},\le 2^{\aleph_{0}})\):  Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets  each with power \(\le  2^{\aleph_{0}}\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
17

Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

18

\(PUT(\aleph_{0},2,\aleph_{0})\):  The union of a denumerable family of pairwise disjoint pairs has a denumerable subset.

19

A real function is analytically representable if and only if it is in Baire's classification. G.Moore [1982], equation (2.3.1).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

20

If \(\{A_{x}: x \in S \}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x \in  S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| = |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore [1982] (1.4.12 and 1.7.8).

21

If \(S\) is well ordered, \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets, and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}|= |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). G\.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
22

\(UT(2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): If every member of an infinite  set of cardinality \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\), then the union has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
23

\((\forall \alpha)(UT(\aleph_{\alpha},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): For every ordinal \(\alpha\), if \(A\) and every member of \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\), then \(|\bigcup A| = \aleph _{\alpha }\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
24

\(C(\aleph_0,2^{(2^{\aleph_0})})\): Every denumerable collection of non-empty sets each with power \(2^{(2^{\aleph_{0}})}\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
25

\(\aleph _{\beta +1}\) is regular for all ordinals \(\beta\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
26

\(UT(\aleph_{0},2^{\aleph_{0}},2^{\aleph_{0}})\): The union of denumerably many sets each of power \(2^{\aleph _{0}}\) has power \(2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
27

\((\forall \alpha)( UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{\alpha}, \aleph_{\alpha}))\): The  union of denumerably many sets each of power \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) has power \(\aleph_{\alpha}\). Moore, G. [1982], p 36.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
28-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) AL20(\(\mathbb Z_p\)): Every vector space \(V\) over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that every linearly independent subset can be extended to a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p. 119, Statement AL20

0
 \(0 = 0\).
28-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) AL20(\(\mathbb Z_p\)): Every vector space \(V\) over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that every linearly independent subset can be extended to a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p. 119, Statement AL20

28-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) AL20(\(\mathbb Z_p\)): Every vector space \(V\) over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that every linearly independent subset can be extended to a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p. 119, Statement AL20

29
 If \(|S| = \aleph_{0}\) and \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families of pairwise disjoint sets and \(|A_{x}| = |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} A_{x}| = |\bigcup^{}_{x\in S} B_{x}|\). Moore, G. [1982], p 324.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
30

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
31

\(UT(\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0},\aleph_{0})\): The countable union theorem:  The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is denumerable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
32

\(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets  has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
33-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,n)\):  Every linearly ordered set of \(n\) element sets has  a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

34

\(\aleph_{1}\) is regular.

35

The union of countably many meager subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is meager. (Meager sets are the same as sets of the first category.) Jech [1973b] p 7 prob 1.7.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
36

Compact T\(_2\) spaces are Loeb. (A space is Loeb if the set of non-empty closed sets has a choice function.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
36

Compact T\(_2\) spaces are Loeb. (A space is Loeb if the set of non-empty closed sets has a choice function.)

36

Compact T\(_2\) spaces are Loeb. (A space is Loeb if the set of non-empty closed sets has a choice function.)

37

Lebesgue measure is countably additive.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

38

\({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets.

39

\(C(\aleph_{1},\infty)\): Every set \(A\) of non-empty sets such that \(\vert A\vert = \aleph_{1}\) has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p. 202.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
40

\(C(WO,\infty)\):  Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
41

\(W_{\aleph _{1}}\): For every cardinal \(m\), \(m \le \aleph_{1}\) or \(\aleph_{1}\le m \).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
42

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem: If a countable family of first order  sentences is satisfiable in a set \(M\) then it is satisfiable in a countable subset of \(M\). (See Moore, G. [1982], p. 251 for references.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
43

\(DC(\omega)\) (DC), Principle of Dependent Choices: If \(S\)  is  a relation on a non-empty set \(A\) and \((\forall x\in A) (\exists y\in A)(x S y)\)  then there is a sequence \(a(0), a(1), a(2), \ldots\) of elements of \(A\) such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(a(n)\mathrel S a(n+1))\).  See Tarski [1948], p 96, Levy [1964], p. 136.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
44

\(DC(\aleph _{1})\):  Given a relation \(R\) such that for every  subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y| < \aleph_{1}\) there is an \(x \in  X\)  with \(Y \mathrel R x\), then there is a function \(f: \aleph_{1} \rightarrow  X\) such that \((\forall\beta < \aleph_{1}) (\{f(\gamma ): \gamma < b \} \mathrel R f(\beta))\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
45-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,n)\): Every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
46-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\infty,K)\): For every \(n\in K\), every set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
47-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,n)\): Every well ordered collection of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
48-K

If \(K\) is a finite subset of \(\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(WO,K)\): For every \(n\in K,\) \(C(WO,n)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
49

Order Extension Principle: Every partial ordering can be extended to a linear ordering.  Tarski [1924], p 78.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
50

Sikorski's  Extension Theorem: Every homomorphism of a subalgebra \(B\) of a Boolean algebra \(A\) into a complete Boolean algebra \(B'\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B'\). Sikorski [1964], p. 141.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
50

Sikorski's  Extension Theorem: Every homomorphism of a subalgebra \(B\) of a Boolean algebra \(A\) into a complete Boolean algebra \(B'\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B'\). Sikorski [1964], p. 141.

50

Sikorski's  Extension Theorem: Every homomorphism of a subalgebra \(B\) of a Boolean algebra \(A\) into a complete Boolean algebra \(B'\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B'\). Sikorski [1964], p. 141.

51

Cofinality Principle: Every linear ordering has a cofinal sub well ordering.  Sierpi\'nski [1918], p 117.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
52

Hahn-Banach Theorem:  If \(V\) is a real vector space and \(p: V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t > 0)( p(tx) = tp(x) )\) and \(S\) is a subspace of \(V\) and \(f:S \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) is linear and satisfies \((\forall  x \in S)( f(x) \le  p(x) )\) then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^{*} : V \rightarrow {\Bbb R}\) such that \(f^{*}\) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^{*}(x) \le p(x))\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
53

For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(m^2\le 2^m\).  Mathias [1979], prob 1336.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
54

For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(m\) adj \(2^{m}\) implies \(m\) is an aleph.  
Note that \(m\) adj \(n\) iff \(m < n\) and \(\neg (\exists p) (m < p < n).\)
Mathias [1979] prob 1337, thm 1338 and prob 1339.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
55

For all infinite cardinals \(m\) and \(n\), if \(m\cdot n = m + n\) then, \(m \le  n\) or \(n \le m\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
56

\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{0}})\neq\aleph_{\omega}\). (\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{0}})\) is Hartogs' aleph, the least \(\aleph\) not \(\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).)
Mathias [1979], p 125.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
57

If \(x\) and \(y\) are Dedekind finite sets then either \(|x|\le |y|\) or \(|y|\le |x|\).
Mathias [1979], p 125.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
58

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\neq\aleph_{\alpha +1}\). (\(\aleph(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}})\) is Hartogs' aleph, the least \(\aleph\) not \(\le 2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\).)
Mathias [1979], p 126.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
59-le

If \((A,\le)\) is a partial ordering that is not a well ordering, then there is no set \(B\) such that \((B,\le)\) (the usual injective cardinal ordering on \(B\)) is isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).
Mathias [1979], p 120.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
60

\(C(\infty,WO)\): Every set of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.
Moore, G. [1982], p 125.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

61

\((\forall n\in\omega, n\ge 2\))\((C(\infty,n))\): For each \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\), every set of \(n\) element  sets has a choice function.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

62

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

63

\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
Jech [1973b], p 172 prob 8.5.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
64

\(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
65

The Krein-Milman Theorem: Let \(K\) be a compact convex set in a locally convex topological vector space \(X\). Then \(K\) has an extreme point. (An extreme point is a point which is not an interior point of any line segment which lies in  \(K\).) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985] p. 177.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
65

The Krein-Milman Theorem: Let \(K\) be a compact convex set in a locally convex topological vector space \(X\). Then \(K\) has an extreme point. (An extreme point is a point which is not an interior point of any line segment which lies in  \(K\).) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985] p. 177.

65

The Krein-Milman Theorem: Let \(K\) be a compact convex set in a locally convex topological vector space \(X\). Then \(K\) has an extreme point. (An extreme point is a point which is not an interior point of any line segment which lies in  \(K\).) Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985] p. 177.

66

Every vector space over a field has a basis.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
67

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
68

Nielsen-Schreier Theorem: Every subgroup of a free group is free.  Jech [1973b], p 12.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
69

Every field has an algebraic closure.  Jech [1973b], p 13.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
70

There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\). Jech [1973b], prob 5.24.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
71-alpha
 

\(W_{\aleph_{\alpha}}\): \((\forall x)(|x|\le\aleph_{\alpha }\) or \(|x|\ge \aleph_{\alpha})\). Jech [1973b], page 119.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
71-alpha
 

\(W_{\aleph_{\alpha}}\): \((\forall x)(|x|\le\aleph_{\alpha }\) or \(|x|\ge \aleph_{\alpha})\). Jech [1973b], page 119.

71-alpha
 

\(W_{\aleph_{\alpha}}\): \((\forall x)(|x|\le\aleph_{\alpha }\) or \(|x|\ge \aleph_{\alpha})\). Jech [1973b], page 119.

72

Artin-Schreier Theorem:  Every field in which \(-1\) is not the sum of squares can be ordered. (The ordering, \(\le \), must satisfy (a) \(a\le b\rightarrow a + c\le b + c\) for all \(c\) and (b) \(c\ge 0\) and \(a\le b\rightarrow a\cdot c\le b\cdot c\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
73

\(\forall n\in\omega\), \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  For every \(n\in\omega\), if \(C\) is an infinite family of \(n\) element sets, then \(C\) has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

0
 \(0 = 0\).
73

\(\forall n\in\omega\), \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  For every \(n\in\omega\), if \(C\) is an infinite family of \(n\) element sets, then \(C\) has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

73

\(\forall n\in\omega\), \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  For every \(n\in\omega\), if \(C\) is an infinite family of \(n\) element sets, then \(C\) has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco [1998b]

74

For every \(A\subseteq\Bbb R\) the following are equivalent:

  1. \(A\) is closed and bounded.
  2. Every sequence \(\{x_{n}\}\subseteq A\) has a convergent subsequence with limit in A.
Jech [1973b], p 21.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
75

If a set has at least two elements, then it can be partitioned into well orderable subsets, each of which has at least two elements.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
75

If a set has at least two elements, then it can be partitioned into well orderable subsets, each of which has at least two elements.

75

If a set has at least two elements, then it can be partitioned into well orderable subsets, each of which has at least two elements.

76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

76

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

77

A linear ordering of a set \(P\) is a well ordering if and only if \(P\) has no infinite descending sequences. Jech [1973b], p 23.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
78

Urysohn's Lemma:  If \(A\) and \(B\) are disjoint closed sets in a normal space \(S\), then there is a continuous \(f:S\rightarrow [0,1]\) which is 1 everywhere in \(A\) and 0 everywhere in \(B\). Urysohn [1925], pp 290-292.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
79

\({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered.  Hilbert [1900], p 263.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
80

\(C(\aleph_{0},2)\):  Every denumerable set of  pairs has  a  choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
81-n

(For \(n\in\omega\)) \(K(n)\): For every set \(S\) there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a one to one function \(f: S \rightarrow {\cal P}^{n}(\alpha)\). (\({\cal P}^{0}(X) = X\) and \({\cal P}^{n+1}(X) = {\cal P}({\cal P}^{n}(X))\). (\(K(0)\) is equivalent to [1 AC]  and \(K(1)\) is equivalent to the selection principle (Form 15)).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
81-n

(For \(n\in\omega\)) \(K(n)\): For every set \(S\) there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a one to one function \(f: S \rightarrow {\cal P}^{n}(\alpha)\). (\({\cal P}^{0}(X) = X\) and \({\cal P}^{n+1}(X) = {\cal P}({\cal P}^{n}(X))\). (\(K(0)\) is equivalent to [1 AC]  and \(K(1)\) is equivalent to the selection principle (Form 15)).

81-n

(For \(n\in\omega\)) \(K(n)\): For every set \(S\) there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a one to one function \(f: S \rightarrow {\cal P}^{n}(\alpha)\). (\({\cal P}^{0}(X) = X\) and \({\cal P}^{n+1}(X) = {\cal P}({\cal P}^{n}(X))\). (\(K(0)\) is equivalent to [1 AC]  and \(K(1)\) is equivalent to the selection principle (Form 15)).

82

\(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
83

\(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
84

\(E(II,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): \((\forall x)(x\) is \(T\)-finite  if and only if \(\cal P(x)\) is Dedekind finite).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
85

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{0})\):  Every family of denumerable sets has  a choice function.  Jech [1973b] p 115 prob 7.13.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
86-alpha

\(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
87-alpha

\(DC(\aleph_{\alpha})\): Given a relation \(R\) such that for every subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\), there is an \(x\in X\) with \(Y\mathrel R x\) then there is a function \(f:\aleph_{\alpha}\to X\) such that (\(\forall\beta < \aleph_{\alpha}\)) \(\{f(\gamma): \gamma < \beta\}\mathrel R f(\beta)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

89

Antichain Principle:  Every partially ordered set has a maximal antichain. Jech [1973b], p 133.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
90

\(LW\):  Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
91

\(PW\):  The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
92

\(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
92

\(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

92

\(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

93

There is a non-measurable subset of \({\Bbb R}\).

94

\(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals  has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
95-F

Existence of Complementary Subspaces over a Field \(F\): If \(F\) is a field, then every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that if \(S\subseteq V\) is a subspace of \(V\), then there is a subspace \(S'\subseteq V\) such that \(S\cap S'= \{0\}\) and \(S\cup S'\) generates \(V\). H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], pp 119ff, and Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.4.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
95-F

Existence of Complementary Subspaces over a Field \(F\): If \(F\) is a field, then every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that if \(S\subseteq V\) is a subspace of \(V\), then there is a subspace \(S'\subseteq V\) such that \(S\cap S'= \{0\}\) and \(S\cup S'\) generates \(V\). H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], pp 119ff, and Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.4.

95-F

Existence of Complementary Subspaces over a Field \(F\): If \(F\) is a field, then every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that if \(S\subseteq V\) is a subspace of \(V\), then there is a subspace \(S'\subseteq V\) such that \(S\cap S'= \{0\}\) and \(S\cup S'\) generates \(V\). H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], pp 119ff, and Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.4.

96

Löwig's Theorem:If \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are both bases for the vector space \(V\) then \(|B_{1}| = |B_{2}|\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
96

Löwig's Theorem:If \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are both bases for the vector space \(V\) then \(|B_{1}| = |B_{2}|\).

96

Löwig's Theorem:If \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are both bases for the vector space \(V\) then \(|B_{1}| = |B_{2}|\).

97

Cardinal Representatives: For every set \(A\) there is a function \(c\) with domain \({\cal P}(A)\) such that for all \(x, y\in {\cal P}(A)\), (i) \(c(x) = c(y) \leftrightarrow x\approx y\) and (ii) \(c(x)\approx x\).  Jech [1973b] p 154.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
98

The set of all finite subsets of a Dedekind finite set is Dedekind finite. Jech [1973b] p 161 prob 11.5.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
99

Rado's Selection Lemma: Let \(\{K(\lambda): \lambda \in\Lambda\}\) be a family  of finite subsets (of \(X\)) and suppose for each finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a function \(\gamma(S): S \rightarrow X\) such that \((\forall\lambda\in S)(\gamma(S)(\lambda)\in K(\lambda))\).  Then there is an \(f: \Lambda\rightarrow X\) such that for every finite \(S\subseteq\Lambda\) there is a finite \(T\) such that \(S\subseteq T\subseteq\Lambda\) and such that \(f\) and \(\gamma (T)\) agree on S.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
100

Weak Partition Principle:  For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\precsim^* y\), then it is not the case that \(y\prec x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
101

Partition Principle:  If \(S\) is a partition of \(M\), then \(S \precsim M\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
102

For all Dedekind finite cardinals \(p\) and \(q\), if \(p^{2} = q^{2}\) then \(p = q\). Jech [1973b], p 162 prob 11.12.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
103

If \((P,<)\) is a linear ordering and \(|P| > \aleph_{1}\) then some initial segment of \(P\) is uncountable. Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.21.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
104

There is a regular uncountable aleph. Jech [1966b], p 165 prob 11.26.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
105

There is a  partially ordered set \((A,\le)\) such that for no set \(B\) is \((B,\le)\) (the ordering  on \(B\) is the usual injective cardinal ordering) isomorphic to \((A,\le)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
106

Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
107
 

M. Hall's Theorem: Let \(\{S(\alpha): \alpha\in A\}\) be a collection of finite subsets (of a set \(X\)) then if

(*) for each finite \(F \subseteq  A\) there is an injective choice function on \(F\)
then there is an injective choice function on \(A\). (That is, a 1-1 function \(f\) such that \((\forall\alpha\in A)(f(\alpha)\in S(\alpha))\).) (According to a theorem of P. Hall (\(*\)) is equivalent to \(\left |\bigcup_{\alpha\in F} S(\alpha)\right|\ge |F|\). P. Hall's theorem does not require the axiom of choice.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
107
 

M. Hall's Theorem: Let \(\{S(\alpha): \alpha\in A\}\) be a collection of finite subsets (of a set \(X\)) then if

(*) for each finite \(F \subseteq  A\) there is an injective choice function on \(F\)
then there is an injective choice function on \(A\). (That is, a 1-1 function \(f\) such that \((\forall\alpha\in A)(f(\alpha)\in S(\alpha))\).) (According to a theorem of P. Hall (\(*\)) is equivalent to \(\left |\bigcup_{\alpha\in F} S(\alpha)\right|\ge |F|\). P. Hall's theorem does not require the axiom of choice.)

107
 

M. Hall's Theorem: Let \(\{S(\alpha): \alpha\in A\}\) be a collection of finite subsets (of a set \(X\)) then if

(*) for each finite \(F \subseteq  A\) there is an injective choice function on \(F\)
then there is an injective choice function on \(A\). (That is, a 1-1 function \(f\) such that \((\forall\alpha\in A)(f(\alpha)\in S(\alpha))\).) (According to a theorem of P. Hall (\(*\)) is equivalent to \(\left |\bigcup_{\alpha\in F} S(\alpha)\right|\ge |F|\). P. Hall's theorem does not require the axiom of choice.)

108

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\) is not the union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
109

Every field \(F\) and every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that each linearly independent set \(A\subseteq V\) can be extended to a basis. H.Rubin/J.~Rubin [1985], pp 119ff.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
109

Every field \(F\) and every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that each linearly independent set \(A\subseteq V\) can be extended to a basis. H.Rubin/J.~Rubin [1985], pp 119ff.

109

Every field \(F\) and every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that each linearly independent set \(A\subseteq V\) can be extended to a basis. H.Rubin/J.~Rubin [1985], pp 119ff.

110

Every vector space over \(\Bbb Q\) has a basis.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
111

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
111

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

111

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

112

\(MC(\infty,LO)\): For every family \(X\) of non-empty sets each of which can be linearly ordered there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
113

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many Spaces: The product of a countable set of compact spaces is compact.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
114

Every A-bounded \(T_2\) topological space is weakly Loeb. (\(A\)-bounded means amorphous subsets are relatively compact. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
115

The product of weakly Loeb \(T_2\) spaces is weakly Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
116

Every compact \(T_2\) space is weakly  Loeb. Weakly Loeb means the set of non-empty closed subsets has a multiple choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
117

If \(\kappa\) is a measurable cardinal, then \(\kappa\) is the \(\kappa\)th inaccessible cardinal.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
118

Every linearly orderable topological space is normal.  Birkhoff [1967], p 241.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
119

van Douwen's choice principle: \(C(\aleph_{0}\),uniformly orderable with order type of the integers): Suppose \(\{ A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) is a set and there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(i\in\omega,\ f(i)\) is an ordering of \(A_{i}\) of type \(\omega^{*}+\omega\) (the usual ordering of the integers), then \(\{A_{i}: i\in\omega\}\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
120-K

If \(K\subseteq\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(LO,K)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty sets each of whose cardinality is in \(K\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
121

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
122

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
123

\(SPI^*\): Uniform weak ultrafilter principle: For each family \(F\) of infinite sets \(\exists f\) such that \(\forall x\in F\), \(f(x)\) is a non-principal ultrafilter on \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
124

Every operator on a Hilbert space with an amorphous base is the direct sum of a finite matrix and  a  scalar operator.  (A set is amorphous if it is not the union of two disjoint infinite sets.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
125

There does not exist an infinite, compact connected \(p\) space. (A \(p\) space is a \(T_2\) space in which the intersection of any well orderable family of open sets is open.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

127

An amorphous power of a compact \(T_2\) space, which as a set is well orderable, is well orderable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
128

Aczel's Realization Principle: On every infinite set there is a Hausdorff topology with an infinite set of non-isolated points.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
129

For every infinite set \(A\), \(A\) admits a partition into sets of order type \(\omega^{*} + \omega\). (For every infinite \(A\), there is a set \(\{\langle C_j,<_j \rangle: j\in J\}\) such that \(\{C_j: j\in J\}\) is a partition of \(A\) and for each \(j\in J\), \(<_j\) is an ordering of \(C_j\) of type \(\omega^* + \omega\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
130

\({\cal P}(\Bbb R)\) is well orderable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
131

\(MC_\omega(\aleph_0,\infty)\): For every denumerable family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
131

\(MC_\omega(\aleph_0,\infty)\): For every denumerable family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

131

\(MC_\omega(\aleph_0,\infty)\): For every denumerable family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
134

If \(X\) is an infinite \(T_1\) space and \(X^{Y}\) is \(T_5\), then \(Y\) is countable. (\(T_5\) is 'hereditarily \(T_4\)'.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
134

If \(X\) is an infinite \(T_1\) space and \(X^{Y}\) is \(T_5\), then \(Y\) is countable. (\(T_5\) is 'hereditarily \(T_4\)'.)

134

If \(X\) is an infinite \(T_1\) space and \(X^{Y}\) is \(T_5\), then \(Y\) is countable. (\(T_5\) is 'hereditarily \(T_4\)'.)

135

If \(X\) is a \(T_2\) space with at least two points and \(X^{Y}\) is hereditarily metacompact then \(Y\) is  countable. (A space is metacompact if every open cover has an open point finite refinement. If \(B\) and \(B'\) are covers of a space \(X\), then \(B'\) is a refinement of \(B\) if \((\forall x\in B')(\exists y\in B)(x\subseteq y)\). \(B\) is point finite if \((\forall t\in X)\) there are only finitely many \(x\in B\) such that \(t\in x\).) van Douwen [1980]

0
 \(0 = 0\).
135

If \(X\) is a \(T_2\) space with at least two points and \(X^{Y}\) is hereditarily metacompact then \(Y\) is  countable. (A space is metacompact if every open cover has an open point finite refinement. If \(B\) and \(B'\) are covers of a space \(X\), then \(B'\) is a refinement of \(B\) if \((\forall x\in B')(\exists y\in B)(x\subseteq y)\). \(B\) is point finite if \((\forall t\in X)\) there are only finitely many \(x\in B\) such that \(t\in x\).) van Douwen [1980]

135

If \(X\) is a \(T_2\) space with at least two points and \(X^{Y}\) is hereditarily metacompact then \(Y\) is  countable. (A space is metacompact if every open cover has an open point finite refinement. If \(B\) and \(B'\) are covers of a space \(X\), then \(B'\) is a refinement of \(B\) if \((\forall x\in B')(\exists y\in B)(x\subseteq y)\). \(B\) is point finite if \((\forall t\in X)\) there are only finitely many \(x\in B\) such that \(t\in x\).) van Douwen [1980]

136-k

Surjective Cardinal Cancellation (depends on \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\)): For all cardinals \(x\) and \(y\), \(kx\le^* ky\) implies \(x\le^* y\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
136-k

Surjective Cardinal Cancellation (depends on \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\)): For all cardinals \(x\) and \(y\), \(kx\le^* ky\) implies \(x\le^* y\).

136-k

Surjective Cardinal Cancellation (depends on \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\)): For all cardinals \(x\) and \(y\), \(kx\le^* ky\) implies \(x\le^* y\).

137-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\). If \(f\) is a 1-1 map from \(k\times X\) into \(k\times Y\) then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i} \) and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i} \) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  X_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  Y_{i})\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
137-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\). If \(f\) is a 1-1 map from \(k\times X\) into \(k\times Y\) then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i} \) and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i} \) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  X_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  Y_{i})\).

137-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega-\{0\}\). If \(f\) is a 1-1 map from \(k\times X\) into \(k\times Y\) then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i} \) and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i} \) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  X_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times  Y_{i})\).

138-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega\).  If \(f\) is a partial map from \(k\times Y\)  onto \(k\times X\) (that is, the domain is a subset of \(k\times Y\)), then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i}\)  and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i}\) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times Y_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup^{}_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times X_{i})\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
138-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega\).  If \(f\) is a partial map from \(k\times Y\)  onto \(k\times X\) (that is, the domain is a subset of \(k\times Y\)), then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i}\)  and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i}\) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times Y_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup^{}_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times X_{i})\).

138-k

Suppose \(k\in\omega\).  If \(f\) is a partial map from \(k\times Y\)  onto \(k\times X\) (that is, the domain is a subset of \(k\times Y\)), then there are partitions \(X = \bigcup_{i \le k} X_{i}\)  and \(Y = \bigcup_{i \le k} Y_{i}\) of \(X\) and \(Y\) such that \(f\) maps \(\bigcup_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times Y_{i})\) onto \(\bigcup^{}_{i \le k} (\{i\} \times X_{i})\).

139

Using the discrete topology on 2, \(2^{\cal P(\omega)}\) is compact.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
139

Using the discrete topology on 2, \(2^{\cal P(\omega)}\) is compact.

139

Using the discrete topology on 2, \(2^{\cal P(\omega)}\) is compact.

140

Let \(\Omega\) be the set of all (undirected) infinite cycles of reals (Graphs whose vertices are real numbers, connected, no loops and each vertex adjacent to  exactly two others). Then there is a function \(f\) on \(\Omega \) such that for all \(s\in\Omega\), \(f(s)\) is a direction along \(s\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
140

Let \(\Omega\) be the set of all (undirected) infinite cycles of reals (Graphs whose vertices are real numbers, connected, no loops and each vertex adjacent to  exactly two others). Then there is a function \(f\) on \(\Omega \) such that for all \(s\in\Omega\), \(f(s)\) is a direction along \(s\).

140

Let \(\Omega\) be the set of all (undirected) infinite cycles of reals (Graphs whose vertices are real numbers, connected, no loops and each vertex adjacent to  exactly two others). Then there is a function \(f\) on \(\Omega \) such that for all \(s\in\Omega\), \(f(s)\) is a direction along \(s\).

141

[14 P(\(n\))] with \(n = 2\):  Let \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\) be a collection of sets such that \(\forall i\in I,\ |A(i)|\le 2\) and suppose \(R\) is a symmetric binary relation on \(\bigcup^{}_{i\in I} A(i)\) such that for all finite \(W\subseteq I\) there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i \in W\}\). Then there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
141

[14 P(\(n\))] with \(n = 2\):  Let \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\) be a collection of sets such that \(\forall i\in I,\ |A(i)|\le 2\) and suppose \(R\) is a symmetric binary relation on \(\bigcup^{}_{i\in I} A(i)\) such that for all finite \(W\subseteq I\) there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i \in W\}\). Then there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\).

141

[14 P(\(n\))] with \(n = 2\):  Let \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\) be a collection of sets such that \(\forall i\in I,\ |A(i)|\le 2\) and suppose \(R\) is a symmetric binary relation on \(\bigcup^{}_{i\in I} A(i)\) such that for all finite \(W\subseteq I\) there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i \in W\}\). Then there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\).

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

142

\(\neg  PB\):  There is a set of reals without the property of Baire.  Jech [1973b], p. 7.

143

\(H(C,TR)\): If \((X,R)\) is a connected relation (\(u\neq v\rightarrow u\mathrel R v\) or \(v\mathrel R u\)) then \(X\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
143

\(H(C,TR)\): If \((X,R)\) is a connected relation (\(u\neq v\rightarrow u\mathrel R v\) or \(v\mathrel R u\)) then \(X\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

143

\(H(C,TR)\): If \((X,R)\) is a connected relation (\(u\neq v\rightarrow u\mathrel R v\) or \(v\mathrel R u\)) then \(X\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

144

Every set is almost well orderable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
144

Every set is almost well orderable.

144

Every set is almost well orderable.

145

Compact \(P_0\)-spaces are Dedekind finite. (A \(P_0\)-space is a topological space in which the intersection of a countable collection of open sets is open.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
145

Compact \(P_0\)-spaces are Dedekind finite. (A \(P_0\)-space is a topological space in which the intersection of a countable collection of open sets is open.)

145

Compact \(P_0\)-spaces are Dedekind finite. (A \(P_0\)-space is a topological space in which the intersection of a countable collection of open sets is open.)

146

\(A(F,A1)\): For every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\), if \(X\) is a continuous finite to one image of an A1 space then \((X,T)\) is  an A1 space. (\((X,T)\) is A1 means if \(U \subseteq  T\) covers \(X\) then \(\exists f : X\rightarrow U\) such that \((\forall x\in X) (x\in f(x)).)\)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
146

\(A(F,A1)\): For every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\), if \(X\) is a continuous finite to one image of an A1 space then \((X,T)\) is  an A1 space. (\((X,T)\) is A1 means if \(U \subseteq  T\) covers \(X\) then \(\exists f : X\rightarrow U\) such that \((\forall x\in X) (x\in f(x)).)\)

146

\(A(F,A1)\): For every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\), if \(X\) is a continuous finite to one image of an A1 space then \((X,T)\) is  an A1 space. (\((X,T)\) is A1 means if \(U \subseteq  T\) covers \(X\) then \(\exists f : X\rightarrow U\) such that \((\forall x\in X) (x\in f(x)).)\)

147

\(A(D2)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\) can be covered by a well ordered family of discrete sets.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
147

\(A(D2)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\) can be covered by a well ordered family of discrete sets.

147

\(A(D2)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\) can be covered by a well ordered family of discrete sets.

148

\(A(W2,B1)\): For every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\), if \(X\) is well ordered, then \(X\) has a well ordered base.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
148

\(A(W2,B1)\): For every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\), if \(X\) is well ordered, then \(X\) has a well ordered base.

148

\(A(W2,B1)\): For every \(T_2\) topological space \((X,T)\), if \(X\) is well ordered, then \(X\) has a well ordered base.

149

\(A(F)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space is a continuous, finite to one image of an \(A1\) space.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
149

\(A(F)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space is a continuous, finite to one image of an \(A1\) space.

149

\(A(F)\):  Every \(T_2\) topological space is a continuous, finite to one image of an \(A1\) space.

150

\(PC(\infty,\aleph_0,\infty)\): Every infinite set of denumerable sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
150

\(PC(\infty,\aleph_0,\infty)\): Every infinite set of denumerable sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

150

\(PC(\infty,\aleph_0,\infty)\): Every infinite set of denumerable sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

151

\(UT(WO,\aleph_{0},WO)\) (\(U_{\aleph_{1}}\)): The union of a well ordered set of denumerable sets is well  orderable. (If \(\kappa\) is a well ordered cardinal, see note 27 for \(UT(WO,\kappa,WO)\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
151

\(UT(WO,\aleph_{0},WO)\) (\(U_{\aleph_{1}}\)): The union of a well ordered set of denumerable sets is well  orderable. (If \(\kappa\) is a well ordered cardinal, see note 27 for \(UT(WO,\kappa,WO)\).)

151

\(UT(WO,\aleph_{0},WO)\) (\(U_{\aleph_{1}}\)): The union of a well ordered set of denumerable sets is well  orderable. (If \(\kappa\) is a well ordered cardinal, see note 27 for \(UT(WO,\kappa,WO)\).)

152

\(D_{\aleph_{0}}\): Every non-well-orderable set is the union of a pairwise disjoint, well orderable family of denumerable sets.  (See note 27 for \(D_{\kappa}\), \(\kappa\) a well ordered cardinal.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
152

\(D_{\aleph_{0}}\): Every non-well-orderable set is the union of a pairwise disjoint, well orderable family of denumerable sets.  (See note 27 for \(D_{\kappa}\), \(\kappa\) a well ordered cardinal.)

152

\(D_{\aleph_{0}}\): Every non-well-orderable set is the union of a pairwise disjoint, well orderable family of denumerable sets.  (See note 27 for \(D_{\kappa}\), \(\kappa\) a well ordered cardinal.)

153

The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact in the weak topology.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
153

The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact in the weak topology.

153

The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact in the weak topology.

154

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many \(T_2\) Spaces: The product of countably many \(T_2\) compact spaces is compact.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
154

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many \(T_2\) Spaces: The product of countably many \(T_2\) compact spaces is compact.

154

Tychonoff's Compactness Theorem for Countably Many \(T_2\) Spaces: The product of countably many \(T_2\) compact spaces is compact.

155
 \(LC\): There are no non-trivial Läuchli continua. (A Läuchli continuum is a strongly connected continuum. Continuum \(\equiv\) compact, connected, Hausdorff space; and strongly connected \(\equiv\) every continuous real valued function is constant.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
155
 \(LC\): There are no non-trivial Läuchli continua. (A Läuchli continuum is a strongly connected continuum. Continuum \(\equiv\) compact, connected, Hausdorff space; and strongly connected \(\equiv\) every continuous real valued function is constant.)

155
 \(LC\): There are no non-trivial Läuchli continua. (A Läuchli continuum is a strongly connected continuum. Continuum \(\equiv\) compact, connected, Hausdorff space; and strongly connected \(\equiv\) every continuous real valued function is constant.)

156

Theorem of Gelfand and Kolmogoroff: Two compact \(T_2\) spaces are  homeomorphic if their rings of real valued continuous functions are isomorphic.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
156

Theorem of Gelfand and Kolmogoroff: Two compact \(T_2\) spaces are  homeomorphic if their rings of real valued continuous functions are isomorphic.

156

Theorem of Gelfand and Kolmogoroff: Two compact \(T_2\) spaces are  homeomorphic if their rings of real valued continuous functions are isomorphic.

157

Theorem of Goodner: A compact \(T_{2}\) space is extremally disconnected (the closure of every open set is open) if and only if each non-empty subset of \(C(X)\) (set of continuous real valued functions on \(X\)) which is pointwise bounded has a supremum.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
157

Theorem of Goodner: A compact \(T_{2}\) space is extremally disconnected (the closure of every open set is open) if and only if each non-empty subset of \(C(X)\) (set of continuous real valued functions on \(X\)) which is pointwise bounded has a supremum.

157

Theorem of Goodner: A compact \(T_{2}\) space is extremally disconnected (the closure of every open set is open) if and only if each non-empty subset of \(C(X)\) (set of continuous real valued functions on \(X\)) which is pointwise bounded has a supremum.

158

In every Hilbert space \(H\), if the closed unit ball is sequentially compact, then \(H\) has an orthonormal basis.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
158

In every Hilbert space \(H\), if the closed unit ball is sequentially compact, then \(H\) has an orthonormal basis.

158

In every Hilbert space \(H\), if the closed unit ball is sequentially compact, then \(H\) has an orthonormal basis.

159

The regular cardinals are cofinal in the class of ordinals.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
159

The regular cardinals are cofinal in the class of ordinals.

159

The regular cardinals are cofinal in the class of ordinals.

160

No Dedekind finite set can be mapped onto an aleph. (See [9 E].)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
160

No Dedekind finite set can be mapped onto an aleph. (See [9 E].)

160

No Dedekind finite set can be mapped onto an aleph. (See [9 E].)

161

Definability of cardinal addition in terms of \(\le\): There is a first order formula whose only non-logical symbol is \( \le \) (for cardinals) that defines cardinal addition.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
161

Definability of cardinal addition in terms of \(\le\): There is a first order formula whose only non-logical symbol is \( \le \) (for cardinals) that defines cardinal addition.

161

Definability of cardinal addition in terms of \(\le\): There is a first order formula whose only non-logical symbol is \( \le \) (for cardinals) that defines cardinal addition.

162

Non-existence of infinite units: There is no infinite cardinal number \(A\) such that \(A + A > A\)  and for all cardinals \(x\) and \(y\), \(x + y = A\rightarrow x = A\) or \(y = A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
162

Non-existence of infinite units: There is no infinite cardinal number \(A\) such that \(A + A > A\)  and for all cardinals \(x\) and \(y\), \(x + y = A\rightarrow x = A\) or \(y = A\).

162

Non-existence of infinite units: There is no infinite cardinal number \(A\) such that \(A + A > A\)  and for all cardinals \(x\) and \(y\), \(x + y = A\rightarrow x = A\) or \(y = A\).

163

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite, Dedekind finite subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
163

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite, Dedekind finite subset.

163

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite, Dedekind finite subset.

164

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite subset with a Dedekind finite power set.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
164

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite subset with a Dedekind finite power set.

164

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite subset with a Dedekind finite power set.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

165

\(C(WO,WO)\):  Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function.

166

\(PC(\infty,2,\infty)\): Every infinite family of pairs has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
166

\(PC(\infty,2,\infty)\): Every infinite family of pairs has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

166

\(PC(\infty,2,\infty)\): Every infinite family of pairs has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

167

\(PKW(\aleph_{0},\ge 2,\infty)\), Partial Kinna-Wagner Principle:  For every denumerable family \(F\) such that for all \(x\in F\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is an infinite subset \(H\subseteq F\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in H\), \(\emptyset\neq f(x) \subsetneq x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
167

\(PKW(\aleph_{0},\ge 2,\infty)\), Partial Kinna-Wagner Principle:  For every denumerable family \(F\) such that for all \(x\in F\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is an infinite subset \(H\subseteq F\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in H\), \(\emptyset\neq f(x) \subsetneq x\).

167

\(PKW(\aleph_{0},\ge 2,\infty)\), Partial Kinna-Wagner Principle:  For every denumerable family \(F\) such that for all \(x\in F\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is an infinite subset \(H\subseteq F\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in H\), \(\emptyset\neq f(x) \subsetneq x\).

168

Dual Cantor-Bernstein Theorem:\((\forall x) (\forall y)(|x| \le^*|y|\) and \(|y|\le^* |x|\) implies  \(|x| = |y|)\) .

0
 \(0 = 0\).
168

Dual Cantor-Bernstein Theorem:\((\forall x) (\forall y)(|x| \le^*|y|\) and \(|y|\le^* |x|\) implies  \(|x| = |y|)\) .

168

Dual Cantor-Bernstein Theorem:\((\forall x) (\forall y)(|x| \le^*|y|\) and \(|y|\le^* |x|\) implies  \(|x| = |y|)\) .

169

There is an uncountable subset of \({\Bbb R}\) without a perfect subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
169

There is an uncountable subset of \({\Bbb R}\) without a perfect subset.

169

There is an uncountable subset of \({\Bbb R}\) without a perfect subset.

170

\(\aleph_{1}\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
170

\(\aleph_{1}\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

170

\(\aleph_{1}\le 2^{\aleph_{0}}\).

171

If \((P,\le)\) is a partial order such that \(P\) is the denumerable union of finite sets and all antichains in \(P\) are finite then for each denumerable family \({\cal D}\) of dense sets there is a \({\cal D}\) generic filter.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
171

If \((P,\le)\) is a partial order such that \(P\) is the denumerable union of finite sets and all antichains in \(P\) are finite then for each denumerable family \({\cal D}\) of dense sets there is a \({\cal D}\) generic filter.

171

If \((P,\le)\) is a partial order such that \(P\) is the denumerable union of finite sets and all antichains in \(P\) are finite then for each denumerable family \({\cal D}\) of dense sets there is a \({\cal D}\) generic filter.

172

For every infinite set \(S\), if \(S\) is hereditarily countable  (that is, every \(y\in TC(S)\) is countable) then \(|TC(S)|= \aleph_{0}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
172

For every infinite set \(S\), if \(S\) is hereditarily countable  (that is, every \(y\in TC(S)\) is countable) then \(|TC(S)|= \aleph_{0}\).

172

For every infinite set \(S\), if \(S\) is hereditarily countable  (that is, every \(y\in TC(S)\) is countable) then \(|TC(S)|= \aleph_{0}\).

173

\(MPL\): Metric spaces are para-Lindelöf.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
173

\(MPL\): Metric spaces are para-Lindelöf.

173

\(MPL\): Metric spaces are para-Lindelöf.

174-alpha

\(RM1,\aleph_{\alpha }\): The representation theorem for multi-algebras with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations:  Assume \((A,F)\) is  a  multi-algebra  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations (and no other operations). Then  there  is  an  algebra \((B,G)\)  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations and an equivalence relation \(E\) on \(B\) such that \((B/E,G/E)\) and \((A,F)\) are isomorphic multi-algebras.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
174-alpha

\(RM1,\aleph_{\alpha }\): The representation theorem for multi-algebras with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations:  Assume \((A,F)\) is  a  multi-algebra  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations (and no other operations). Then  there  is  an  algebra \((B,G)\)  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations and an equivalence relation \(E\) on \(B\) such that \((B/E,G/E)\) and \((A,F)\) are isomorphic multi-algebras.

174-alpha

\(RM1,\aleph_{\alpha }\): The representation theorem for multi-algebras with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations:  Assume \((A,F)\) is  a  multi-algebra  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations (and no other operations). Then  there  is  an  algebra \((B,G)\)  with \(\aleph_{\alpha }\) unary operations and an equivalence relation \(E\) on \(B\) such that \((B/E,G/E)\) and \((A,F)\) are isomorphic multi-algebras.

175

Transitivity Condition: For all sets \(x\), there is a set \(u\) and a function \(f\) such that \(u\) is transitive and \(f\) is a one to one function from \(x\) onto \(u\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
175

Transitivity Condition: For all sets \(x\), there is a set \(u\) and a function \(f\) such that \(u\) is transitive and \(f\) is a one to one function from \(x\) onto \(u\).

175

Transitivity Condition: For all sets \(x\), there is a set \(u\) and a function \(f\) such that \(u\) is transitive and \(f\) is a one to one function from \(x\) onto \(u\).

176

Every infinite, locally finite group has an infinite Abelian subgroup. (Locally finite means every finite subset generates a finite subgroup.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
176

Every infinite, locally finite group has an infinite Abelian subgroup. (Locally finite means every finite subset generates a finite subgroup.)

176

Every infinite, locally finite group has an infinite Abelian subgroup. (Locally finite means every finite subset generates a finite subgroup.)

177

An infinite box product of regular \(T_1\) spaces, each of cardinality greater than 1, is neither first countable nor connected.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
177

An infinite box product of regular \(T_1\) spaces, each of cardinality greater than 1, is neither first countable nor connected.

177

An infinite box product of regular \(T_1\) spaces, each of cardinality greater than 1, is neither first countable nor connected.

178-n-N

If  \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\) and \(N \subseteq \{ 1, 2, \ldots , n-1 \}\), \(N \neq\emptyset\), \(MC(\infty,n, N)\):  If \(X\) is any set of \(n\)-element sets then  there is  a function \(f\) with domain \(X\) such that for all \(A\in X\), \(f(A)\subseteq A\) and \(|f(A)|\in N\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
178-n-N

If  \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\) and \(N \subseteq \{ 1, 2, \ldots , n-1 \}\), \(N \neq\emptyset\), \(MC(\infty,n, N)\):  If \(X\) is any set of \(n\)-element sets then  there is  a function \(f\) with domain \(X\) such that for all \(A\in X\), \(f(A)\subseteq A\) and \(|f(A)|\in N\).

178-n-N

If  \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\) and \(N \subseteq \{ 1, 2, \ldots , n-1 \}\), \(N \neq\emptyset\), \(MC(\infty,n, N)\):  If \(X\) is any set of \(n\)-element sets then  there is  a function \(f\) with domain \(X\) such that for all \(A\in X\), \(f(A)\subseteq A\) and \(|f(A)|\in N\).

179-epsilon

Suppose  \(\epsilon > 0\) is an ordinal. \(\forall x\), \(x\in W(\epsilon\)).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
179-epsilon

Suppose  \(\epsilon > 0\) is an ordinal. \(\forall x\), \(x\in W(\epsilon\)).

179-epsilon

Suppose  \(\epsilon > 0\) is an ordinal. \(\forall x\), \(x\in W(\epsilon\)).

180

Every Abelian group has a divisible hull.  (If \(A\) and \(B\)  are groups, \(B\) is a divisible hull of \(A\) means \(B\) is a divisible group, \(A\) is a subgroup of \(B\) and for every non-zero \(b \in  B\), \(\exists  n \in \omega \)  such that \(0\neq nb\in A\).)  Fuchs [1970], Theorem 24.4 p 107.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
180

Every Abelian group has a divisible hull.  (If \(A\) and \(B\)  are groups, \(B\) is a divisible hull of \(A\) means \(B\) is a divisible group, \(A\) is a subgroup of \(B\) and for every non-zero \(b \in  B\), \(\exists  n \in \omega \)  such that \(0\neq nb\in A\).)  Fuchs [1970], Theorem 24.4 p 107.

180

Every Abelian group has a divisible hull.  (If \(A\) and \(B\)  are groups, \(B\) is a divisible hull of \(A\) means \(B\) is a divisible group, \(A\) is a subgroup of \(B\) and for every non-zero \(b \in  B\), \(\exists  n \in \omega \)  such that \(0\neq nb\in A\).)  Fuchs [1970], Theorem 24.4 p 107.

181

\(C(2^{\aleph_0},\infty)\): Every set \(X\) of non-empty sets such that \(|X|=2^{\aleph_0}\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
181

\(C(2^{\aleph_0},\infty)\): Every set \(X\) of non-empty sets such that \(|X|=2^{\aleph_0}\) has a choice function.

181

\(C(2^{\aleph_0},\infty)\): Every set \(X\) of non-empty sets such that \(|X|=2^{\aleph_0}\) has a choice function.

182

There is an aleph whose cofinality is greater than \(\aleph_{0}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
182

There is an aleph whose cofinality is greater than \(\aleph_{0}\).

182

There is an aleph whose cofinality is greater than \(\aleph_{0}\).

183-alpha

There are no \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) minimal  sets.  That is, there are no sets \(X\) such that

  1. \(|X|\) is incomparable with \(\aleph_{\alpha}\)
  2. \(\aleph_{\beta}<|X|\) for every \(\beta < \alpha \) and
  3. \(\forall Y\subseteq X, |Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\) or \(|X-Y| <\aleph_{\alpha}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
183-alpha

There are no \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) minimal  sets.  That is, there are no sets \(X\) such that

  1. \(|X|\) is incomparable with \(\aleph_{\alpha}\)
  2. \(\aleph_{\beta}<|X|\) for every \(\beta < \alpha \) and
  3. \(\forall Y\subseteq X, |Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\) or \(|X-Y| <\aleph_{\alpha}\).

183-alpha

There are no \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) minimal  sets.  That is, there are no sets \(X\) such that

  1. \(|X|\) is incomparable with \(\aleph_{\alpha}\)
  2. \(\aleph_{\beta}<|X|\) for every \(\beta < \alpha \) and
  3. \(\forall Y\subseteq X, |Y|<\aleph_{\alpha}\) or \(|X-Y| <\aleph_{\alpha}\).

184

Existence of a double uniformization: For all \(X\) and \(Y\), for all \(E\subseteq X\times Y\), if there is an infinite cardinal \(\kappa\) satisfying:

  1. \(\forall y_0\in Y\), \(|\{(x,y_0): x\in X\}\cap E| =\kappa\) and
  2. \(\forall x_0\in X\), \(|\{(x_0,y): y\in Y\}\cap E| = \kappa\),
then \(\exists U\subseteq E\) such that for all \((x,y)\in E, \exists !z\in X\) such that \((z,y)\in U\) and \(\exists !z\in Y\) such that \((x,z)\in U\). (\(U\) is called a double uniformization of \(E\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
184

Existence of a double uniformization: For all \(X\) and \(Y\), for all \(E\subseteq X\times Y\), if there is an infinite cardinal \(\kappa\) satisfying:

  1. \(\forall y_0\in Y\), \(|\{(x,y_0): x\in X\}\cap E| =\kappa\) and
  2. \(\forall x_0\in X\), \(|\{(x_0,y): y\in Y\}\cap E| = \kappa\),
then \(\exists U\subseteq E\) such that for all \((x,y)\in E, \exists !z\in X\) such that \((z,y)\in U\) and \(\exists !z\in Y\) such that \((x,z)\in U\). (\(U\) is called a double uniformization of \(E\).)

184

Existence of a double uniformization: For all \(X\) and \(Y\), for all \(E\subseteq X\times Y\), if there is an infinite cardinal \(\kappa\) satisfying:

  1. \(\forall y_0\in Y\), \(|\{(x,y_0): x\in X\}\cap E| =\kappa\) and
  2. \(\forall x_0\in X\), \(|\{(x_0,y): y\in Y\}\cap E| = \kappa\),
then \(\exists U\subseteq E\) such that for all \((x,y)\in E, \exists !z\in X\) such that \((z,y)\in U\) and \(\exists !z\in Y\) such that \((x,z)\in U\). (\(U\) is called a double uniformization of \(E\).)

185

Every linearly ordered Dedekind finite set is finite.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
186

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a least upper bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
186

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a least upper bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

186

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a least upper bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

187

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a greatest lower bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
187

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a greatest lower bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

187

Every pair of cardinal numbers has a greatest lower bound (in the usual cardinal ordering.)

188

\(EP\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is a projective Abelian group \(G\) and a homomorphism from \(G\) onto \(A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
188

\(EP\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is a projective Abelian group \(G\) and a homomorphism from \(G\) onto \(A\).

188

\(EP\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is a projective Abelian group \(G\) and a homomorphism from \(G\) onto \(A\).

189

\(EI\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is an injective Abelian group \(G\) and a one to one homomorphism from \(A\) into \(G\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
189

\(EI\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is an injective Abelian group \(G\) and a one to one homomorphism from \(A\) into \(G\).

189

\(EI\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is an injective Abelian group \(G\) and a one to one homomorphism from \(A\) into \(G\).

190

There is a non-trivial injective Abelian group.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
190

There is a non-trivial injective Abelian group.

190

There is a non-trivial injective Abelian group.

191

\(SVC\): There is a set \(S\) such that for every set \(a\), there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a function from \(S\times\alpha\) onto \(a\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
191

\(SVC\): There is a set \(S\) such that for every set \(a\), there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a function from \(S\times\alpha\) onto \(a\).

191

\(SVC\): There is a set \(S\) such that for every set \(a\), there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a function from \(S\times\alpha\) onto \(a\).

192

\(EP\) sets: For every set \(A\) there is a projective set \(X\) and a function from \(X\) onto \(A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
192

\(EP\) sets: For every set \(A\) there is a projective set \(X\) and a function from \(X\) onto \(A\).

192

\(EP\) sets: For every set \(A\) there is a projective set \(X\) and a function from \(X\) onto \(A\).

193

\(EFP\ Ab\): Every Abelian group is a homomorphic image of a free projective Abelian group.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
193

\(EFP\ Ab\): Every Abelian group is a homomorphic image of a free projective Abelian group.

193

\(EFP\ Ab\): Every Abelian group is a homomorphic image of a free projective Abelian group.

194

\(C(\varPi^1_2)\) or \(AC(\varPi^1_2)\): If \(P\in \omega\times{}^{\omega}\omega\), \(P\) has domain \(\omega\), and \(P\) is in \(\varPi^1_2\), then there is a sequence of elements \(\langle x_{k}: k\in\omega\rangle\) of \({}^{\omega}\omega\) with \(\langle k,x_{k}\rangle \in P\) for all \(k\in\omega\). Kanovei [1979].

0
 \(0 = 0\).
194

\(C(\varPi^1_2)\) or \(AC(\varPi^1_2)\): If \(P\in \omega\times{}^{\omega}\omega\), \(P\) has domain \(\omega\), and \(P\) is in \(\varPi^1_2\), then there is a sequence of elements \(\langle x_{k}: k\in\omega\rangle\) of \({}^{\omega}\omega\) with \(\langle k,x_{k}\rangle \in P\) for all \(k\in\omega\). Kanovei [1979].

194

\(C(\varPi^1_2)\) or \(AC(\varPi^1_2)\): If \(P\in \omega\times{}^{\omega}\omega\), \(P\) has domain \(\omega\), and \(P\) is in \(\varPi^1_2\), then there is a sequence of elements \(\langle x_{k}: k\in\omega\rangle\) of \({}^{\omega}\omega\) with \(\langle k,x_{k}\rangle \in P\) for all \(k\in\omega\). Kanovei [1979].

195

Every general linear system has a linear global reaction.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
195

Every general linear system has a linear global reaction.

195

Every general linear system has a linear global reaction.

196-alpha

\(\aleph_{\alpha}\) and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) are not both measurable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
196-alpha

\(\aleph_{\alpha}\) and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) are not both measurable.

196-alpha

\(\aleph_{\alpha}\) and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) are not both measurable.

197

\({\Bbb R}^{2}\) is the union of three sets \(C\) with the property that for all \(x\in C\) there is a straight line \(L\) such that \(L\cap C = \{x\}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
197

\({\Bbb R}^{2}\) is the union of three sets \(C\) with the property that for all \(x\in C\) there is a straight line \(L\) such that \(L\cap C = \{x\}\).

197

\({\Bbb R}^{2}\) is the union of three sets \(C\) with the property that for all \(x\in C\) there is a straight line \(L\) such that \(L\cap C = \{x\}\).

198

For every set \(S\), if the only linearly orderable subsets of \(S\) are the finite subsets of \(S\), then either \(S\) is finite or \(S\) has an amorphous subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
198

For every set \(S\), if the only linearly orderable subsets of \(S\) are the finite subsets of \(S\), then either \(S\) is finite or \(S\) has an amorphous subset.

198

For every set \(S\), if the only linearly orderable subsets of \(S\) are the finite subsets of \(S\), then either \(S\) is finite or \(S\) has an amorphous subset.

199(\(n\))

(For \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\)) If all \(\varSigma^{1}_{n}\), Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega }\omega\) are finite, then all \(\varPi^1_n\) Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega} \omega\) are finite.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
199(\(n\))

(For \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\)) If all \(\varSigma^{1}_{n}\), Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega }\omega\) are finite, then all \(\varPi^1_n\) Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega} \omega\) are finite.

199(\(n\))

(For \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\)) If all \(\varSigma^{1}_{n}\), Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega }\omega\) are finite, then all \(\varPi^1_n\) Dedekind finite subsets of \({}^{\omega} \omega\) are finite.

200

For all infinite \(x\), \(|2^{x}| = |x!|\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
200

For all infinite \(x\), \(|2^{x}| = |x!|\).

200

For all infinite \(x\), \(|2^{x}| = |x!|\).

201

Linking Axiom for Boolean Algebras: Every Boolean algebra has a maximal linked system. (\(L\subseteq B\) is linked if \(a\wedge b\neq 0\) for all \(a\) and \(b \in L\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
201

Linking Axiom for Boolean Algebras: Every Boolean algebra has a maximal linked system. (\(L\subseteq B\) is linked if \(a\wedge b\neq 0\) for all \(a\) and \(b \in L\).)

201

Linking Axiom for Boolean Algebras: Every Boolean algebra has a maximal linked system. (\(L\subseteq B\) is linked if \(a\wedge b\neq 0\) for all \(a\) and \(b \in L\).)

202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

202

\(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has  a choice function.

203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

203

\(C\)(disjoint,\(\subseteq\Bbb R)\): Every partition of \({\cal P}(\omega)\) into non-empty subsets has a choice function.

204

For every infinite \(X\), there is a function from \(X\) onto \(2X\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
204

For every infinite \(X\), there is a function from \(X\) onto \(2X\).

204

For every infinite \(X\), there is a function from \(X\) onto \(2X\).

205

For all cardinals \(m\) and \(n\), if \(m\le^* n\) and \(\neg (n\le^* m)\) then there is a cardinal \(k \le n\) such that \(m\le^* k\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
205

For all cardinals \(m\) and \(n\), if \(m\le^* n\) and \(\neg (n\le^* m)\) then there is a cardinal \(k \le n\) such that \(m\le^* k\).

205

For all cardinals \(m\) and \(n\), if \(m\le^* n\) and \(\neg (n\le^* m)\) then there is a cardinal \(k \le n\) such that \(m\le^* k\).

206

The existence of a non-principal ultrafilter: There exists an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal ultrafilter on \(X\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
206

The existence of a non-principal ultrafilter: There exists an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal ultrafilter on \(X\).

206

The existence of a non-principal ultrafilter: There exists an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal ultrafilter on \(X\).

207-alpha

\(UT(\aleph_{\alpha },\aleph_{\alpha}, <2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\): The union of \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) sets each of cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) has cardinality less than \(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
207-alpha

\(UT(\aleph_{\alpha },\aleph_{\alpha}, <2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\): The union of \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) sets each of cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) has cardinality less than \(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}}\).

207-alpha

\(UT(\aleph_{\alpha },\aleph_{\alpha}, <2^{\aleph_{\alpha }})\): The union of \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) sets each of cardinality \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) has cardinality less than \(2^{\aleph_{\alpha}}\).

208

For all ordinals \(\alpha\), \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\le 2^{\aleph_\alpha}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
208

For all ordinals \(\alpha\), \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\le 2^{\aleph_\alpha}\).

208

For all ordinals \(\alpha\), \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\le 2^{\aleph_\alpha}\).

209

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that for all \(X\), if \(X\) is a denumerable union of denumerable sets then \({\cal P}(X)\) cannot be partitioned into \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) non-empty sets.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
209

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that for all \(X\), if \(X\) is a denumerable union of denumerable sets then \({\cal P}(X)\) cannot be partitioned into \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) non-empty sets.

209

There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that for all \(X\), if \(X\) is a denumerable union of denumerable sets then \({\cal P}(X)\) cannot be partitioned into \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) non-empty sets.

210

The commutator subgroup of a free group is free.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
210

The commutator subgroup of a free group is free.

210

The commutator subgroup of a free group is free.

211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

211

\(DCR\): Dependent choice for relations on \(\Bbb R\): If \(R\subseteq\Bbb R\times\Bbb R\) satisfies \((\forall x\in \Bbb R)(\exists y\in\Bbb R)(x\mathrel R y)\) then there is a sequence \(\langle x(n): n\in\omega\rangle\) of real numbers such that \((\forall n\in\omega)(x(n)\mathrel R x(n+1))\).

212

\(C(2^{\aleph_{0}},\subseteq{\Bbb R})\): If \(R\) is a relation on \({\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), there is a \(y\in{\Bbb R}\) such that \(x\mathrel R y\), then there is a function \(f: {\Bbb R} \rightarrow{\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), \(x\mathrel R f(x)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
212

\(C(2^{\aleph_{0}},\subseteq{\Bbb R})\): If \(R\) is a relation on \({\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), there is a \(y\in{\Bbb R}\) such that \(x\mathrel R y\), then there is a function \(f: {\Bbb R} \rightarrow{\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), \(x\mathrel R f(x)\).

212

\(C(2^{\aleph_{0}},\subseteq{\Bbb R})\): If \(R\) is a relation on \({\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), there is a \(y\in{\Bbb R}\) such that \(x\mathrel R y\), then there is a function \(f: {\Bbb R} \rightarrow{\Bbb R}\) such that for all \(x\in{\Bbb R}\), \(x\mathrel R f(x)\).

213

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{1})\): If \((\forall y\in X)(|y| = \aleph_{1})\) then \(X\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
213

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{1})\): If \((\forall y\in X)(|y| = \aleph_{1})\) then \(X\) has a choice function.

213

\(C(\infty,\aleph_{1})\): If \((\forall y\in X)(|y| = \aleph_{1})\) then \(X\) has a choice function.

214

\(Z(\omega)\): For every family \(A\) of infinite sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in A\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty subset of \(y\) and \(|f(y)|=\aleph_{0}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
214

\(Z(\omega)\): For every family \(A\) of infinite sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in A\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty subset of \(y\) and \(|f(y)|=\aleph_{0}\).

214

\(Z(\omega)\): For every family \(A\) of infinite sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in A\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty subset of \(y\) and \(|f(y)|=\aleph_{0}\).

215

If \((\forall y\subseteq X)(y\) can be linearly ordered implies \(y\) is finite), then \(X\) is finite.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
215

If \((\forall y\subseteq X)(y\) can be linearly ordered implies \(y\) is finite), then \(X\) is finite.

215

If \((\forall y\subseteq X)(y\) can be linearly ordered implies \(y\) is finite), then \(X\) is finite.

216

Every infinite tree has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
216

Every infinite tree has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

216

Every infinite tree has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

217

Every infinite partially ordered set has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
217

Every infinite partially ordered set has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

217

Every infinite partially ordered set has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

218

\((\forall n\in\omega - \{0\}) MC(\infty,\infty \), relatively prime to \(n\)): \(\forall n\in\omega -\{0\}\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets, then  there  is  a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

219

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0\}) MC(\infty,WO\), relatively prime to \(n\)): For all non-zero \(n\in \omega\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty well orderable sets, then there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\), and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
219

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0\}) MC(\infty,WO\), relatively prime to \(n\)): For all non-zero \(n\in \omega\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty well orderable sets, then there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\), and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

219

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0\}) MC(\infty,WO\), relatively prime to \(n\)): For all non-zero \(n\in \omega\), if \(X\) is a set of non-empty well orderable sets, then there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\), and \(|f(x)|\) is relatively prime to \(n\).

220-p

Suppose \(p\in\omega\) and \(p\) is a prime. Any two elementary Abelian \(p\)-groups (all non-trivial elements have order \(p\)) of the same cardinality are isomorphic.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
220-p

Suppose \(p\in\omega\) and \(p\) is a prime. Any two elementary Abelian \(p\)-groups (all non-trivial elements have order \(p\)) of the same cardinality are isomorphic.

220-p

Suppose \(p\in\omega\) and \(p\) is a prime. Any two elementary Abelian \(p\)-groups (all non-trivial elements have order \(p\)) of the same cardinality are isomorphic.

221

For all infinite \(X\), there is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
221

For all infinite \(X\), there is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

221

For all infinite \(X\), there is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

222

There is a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(\omega)\).

223

There is an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
223

There is an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

223

There is an infinite set \(X\) and a non-principal measure on \(\cal P(X)\).

224

There is a partition of the real line into \(\aleph_1\) Borel sets \(\{B_\alpha: \alpha<\aleph_1\}\) such that for some \(\beta <\aleph_1\), \(\forall\alpha <\aleph_1\), \(B_{\alpha}\in G_{\beta}\). (\(G_\beta\) for \(\beta < \aleph_1\) is defined by induction, \(G_0=\{A: A\) is an open subset of \({\Bbb R}\}\) and for \(\beta > 0\),

  • \(G_\beta =\left\{\bigcup^\infty_{i=0}A_{i}: (\forall i\in\omega) (\exists\xi <\beta)(A_i\in G_\xi)\,\right\}\) if \(\beta\) is even and
  • \(G_\beta = \left\{\bigcap^\infty_{i=0}A_{i}: (\forall i\in\omega) (\exists \xi < \beta)(A_{i}\in G_\xi)\,\right\}\) if \(\beta\) is odd.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
224

There is a partition of the real line into \(\aleph_1\) Borel sets \(\{B_\alpha: \alpha<\aleph_1\}\) such that for some \(\beta <\aleph_1\), \(\forall\alpha <\aleph_1\), \(B_{\alpha}\in G_{\beta}\). (\(G_\beta\) for \(\beta < \aleph_1\) is defined by induction, \(G_0=\{A: A\) is an open subset of \({\Bbb R}\}\) and for \(\beta > 0\),

  • \(G_\beta =\left\{\bigcup^\infty_{i=0}A_{i}: (\forall i\in\omega) (\exists\xi <\beta)(A_i\in G_\xi)\,\right\}\) if \(\beta\) is even and
  • \(G_\beta = \left\{\bigcap^\infty_{i=0}A_{i}: (\forall i\in\omega) (\exists \xi < \beta)(A_{i}\in G_\xi)\,\right\}\) if \(\beta\) is odd.)

224

There is a partition of the real line into \(\aleph_1\) Borel sets \(\{B_\alpha: \alpha<\aleph_1\}\) such that for some \(\beta <\aleph_1\), \(\forall\alpha <\aleph_1\), \(B_{\alpha}\in G_{\beta}\). (\(G_\beta\) for \(\beta < \aleph_1\) is defined by induction, \(G_0=\{A: A\) is an open subset of \({\Bbb R}\}\) and for \(\beta > 0\),

  • \(G_\beta =\left\{\bigcup^\infty_{i=0}A_{i}: (\forall i\in\omega) (\exists\xi <\beta)(A_i\in G_\xi)\,\right\}\) if \(\beta\) is even and
  • \(G_\beta = \left\{\bigcap^\infty_{i=0}A_{i}: (\forall i\in\omega) (\exists \xi < \beta)(A_{i}\in G_\xi)\,\right\}\) if \(\beta\) is odd.)

225

Every proper filter on \(\omega\) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
225

Every proper filter on \(\omega\) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

225

Every proper filter on \(\omega\) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

226

Let \(R\) be a commutative ring with identity, \(B\) a proper subring containing 1 and \(q\) a prime ideal in \(B\). Then there is a subring \(A\) of \(R\) and a prime ideal \(p\) in \(A\) such that

  1. \(B\subseteq A\)
  2. \(q = B\cap p\)
  3. \(R - p\) is multiplicatively closed and
  4. if \(A\neq R\),
then \(R - A\) is multiplicatively closed.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
226

Let \(R\) be a commutative ring with identity, \(B\) a proper subring containing 1 and \(q\) a prime ideal in \(B\). Then there is a subring \(A\) of \(R\) and a prime ideal \(p\) in \(A\) such that

  1. \(B\subseteq A\)
  2. \(q = B\cap p\)
  3. \(R - p\) is multiplicatively closed and
  4. if \(A\neq R\),
then \(R - A\) is multiplicatively closed.

226

Let \(R\) be a commutative ring with identity, \(B\) a proper subring containing 1 and \(q\) a prime ideal in \(B\). Then there is a subring \(A\) of \(R\) and a prime ideal \(p\) in \(A\) such that

  1. \(B\subseteq A\)
  2. \(q = B\cap p\)
  3. \(R - p\) is multiplicatively closed and
  4. if \(A\neq R\),
then \(R - A\) is multiplicatively closed.

227

For all groups \(G\), if every finite subgroup of \(G\) can be fully ordered then \(G\) can be fully ordered.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
227

For all groups \(G\), if every finite subgroup of \(G\) can be fully ordered then \(G\) can be fully ordered.

227

For all groups \(G\), if every finite subgroup of \(G\) can be fully ordered then \(G\) can be fully ordered.

228

Every torsion free Abelian group can be fully ordered.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
228

Every torsion free Abelian group can be fully ordered.

228

Every torsion free Abelian group can be fully ordered.

229

If \((G,\circ,\le)\) is a partially ordered group, then \(\le\) can be extended to a linear order on \(G\) if and only if for every finite set \(\{a_{1},\ldots, a_{n}\}\subseteq G\), with \(a_{i}\neq\) the identity for \(i = 1\) to \(n\), the signs \(\epsilon_{1}, \ldots,\epsilon_{n}\) (\(\epsilon_{i} = \pm 1\)) can be chosen so that \(P\cap S(a^{\epsilon_{1}}_{1},\ldots,a^{\epsilon_{n}}_{n})=\emptyset\) (where \(S(b_{1},\ldots,b_{n})\) is the normal sub-semi-group of \(G\) generated by \(b_{1},\ldots, b_{n}\) and \(P = \{g\in G: e\le g\}\) where \(e\) is the identity of \(G\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
229

If \((G,\circ,\le)\) is a partially ordered group, then \(\le\) can be extended to a linear order on \(G\) if and only if for every finite set \(\{a_{1},\ldots, a_{n}\}\subseteq G\), with \(a_{i}\neq\) the identity for \(i = 1\) to \(n\), the signs \(\epsilon_{1}, \ldots,\epsilon_{n}\) (\(\epsilon_{i} = \pm 1\)) can be chosen so that \(P\cap S(a^{\epsilon_{1}}_{1},\ldots,a^{\epsilon_{n}}_{n})=\emptyset\) (where \(S(b_{1},\ldots,b_{n})\) is the normal sub-semi-group of \(G\) generated by \(b_{1},\ldots, b_{n}\) and \(P = \{g\in G: e\le g\}\) where \(e\) is the identity of \(G\).)

229

If \((G,\circ,\le)\) is a partially ordered group, then \(\le\) can be extended to a linear order on \(G\) if and only if for every finite set \(\{a_{1},\ldots, a_{n}\}\subseteq G\), with \(a_{i}\neq\) the identity for \(i = 1\) to \(n\), the signs \(\epsilon_{1}, \ldots,\epsilon_{n}\) (\(\epsilon_{i} = \pm 1\)) can be chosen so that \(P\cap S(a^{\epsilon_{1}}_{1},\ldots,a^{\epsilon_{n}}_{n})=\emptyset\) (where \(S(b_{1},\ldots,b_{n})\) is the normal sub-semi-group of \(G\) generated by \(b_{1},\ldots, b_{n}\) and \(P = \{g\in G: e\le g\}\) where \(e\) is the identity of \(G\).)

230

\(L^{1} = HOD\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
230

\(L^{1} = HOD\).

230

\(L^{1} = HOD\).

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

231

\(UT(WO,WO,WO)\): The union of a well ordered collection of well orderable sets is well orderable.

232

Every metric space \((X,d)\) has a \(\sigma\)-point finite base.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
232

Every metric space \((X,d)\) has a \(\sigma\)-point finite base.

232

Every metric space \((X,d)\) has a \(\sigma\)-point finite base.

233

Artin-Schreier theorem: If a field has an algebraic closure it is unique up to isomorphism.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
233

Artin-Schreier theorem: If a field has an algebraic closure it is unique up to isomorphism.

233

Artin-Schreier theorem: If a field has an algebraic closure it is unique up to isomorphism.

234

There is a non-Ramsey set: There is a set \(A\) of infinite subsets of \(\omega\) such that for every infinite subset \(N\) of \(\omega\), \(N\) has a subset which is in \(A\) and a subset which is not in \(A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
234

There is a non-Ramsey set: There is a set \(A\) of infinite subsets of \(\omega\) such that for every infinite subset \(N\) of \(\omega\), \(N\) has a subset which is in \(A\) and a subset which is not in \(A\).

234

There is a non-Ramsey set: There is a set \(A\) of infinite subsets of \(\omega\) such that for every infinite subset \(N\) of \(\omega\), \(N\) has a subset which is in \(A\) and a subset which is not in \(A\).

235

If \(V\) is a vector space and \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are bases for \(V\) then \(|B_{1}|\) and \(|B_{2}|\) are comparable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
235

If \(V\) is a vector space and \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are bases for \(V\) then \(|B_{1}|\) and \(|B_{2}|\) are comparable.

235

If \(V\) is a vector space and \(B_{1}\) and \(B_{2}\) are bases for \(V\) then \(|B_{1}|\) and \(|B_{2}|\) are comparable.

236

If \(V\) is a vector space with a basis and \(S\) is a linearly independent subset of \(V\) such that no proper extension of \(S\) is a basis for \(V\), then \(S\) is a basis for \(V\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
236

If \(V\) is a vector space with a basis and \(S\) is a linearly independent subset of \(V\) such that no proper extension of \(S\) is a basis for \(V\), then \(S\) is a basis for \(V\).

236

If \(V\) is a vector space with a basis and \(S\) is a linearly independent subset of \(V\) such that no proper extension of \(S\) is a basis for \(V\), then \(S\) is a basis for \(V\).

237

The order of any group is divisible by the order of any of its subgroups, (i.e., if \(H\) is a subgroup of \(G\) then there is a set \(A\) such that \(|H\times A| = |G|\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
237

The order of any group is divisible by the order of any of its subgroups, (i.e., if \(H\) is a subgroup of \(G\) then there is a set \(A\) such that \(|H\times A| = |G|\).)

237

The order of any group is divisible by the order of any of its subgroups, (i.e., if \(H\) is a subgroup of \(G\) then there is a set \(A\) such that \(|H\times A| = |G|\).)

238

Every elementary Abelian group (that is, for some prime \(p\) every non identity element has order \(p\)) is the direct sum of cyclic subgroups.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
238

Every elementary Abelian group (that is, for some prime \(p\) every non identity element has order \(p\)) is the direct sum of cyclic subgroups.

238

Every elementary Abelian group (that is, for some prime \(p\) every non identity element has order \(p\)) is the direct sum of cyclic subgroups.

239

AL20(\(\mathbb Q\)):  Every vector \(V\) space over \(\mathbb Q\) has the property that every linearly independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis. Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p.119, AL20.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
239

AL20(\(\mathbb Q\)):  Every vector \(V\) space over \(\mathbb Q\) has the property that every linearly independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis. Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p.119, AL20.

239

AL20(\(\mathbb Q\)):  Every vector \(V\) space over \(\mathbb Q\) has the property that every linearly independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis. Rubin, H./Rubin, J. [1985], p.119, AL20.

240

If a group \(G\) satisfies "every ascending chain of subgroups is finite", then every subgroup of \(G\) is finitely generated.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
240

If a group \(G\) satisfies "every ascending chain of subgroups is finite", then every subgroup of \(G\) is finitely generated.

240

If a group \(G\) satisfies "every ascending chain of subgroups is finite", then every subgroup of \(G\) is finitely generated.

241

Every algebraic closure of \(\Bbb Q\) has a real closed subfield.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
241

Every algebraic closure of \(\Bbb Q\) has a real closed subfield.

241

Every algebraic closure of \(\Bbb Q\) has a real closed subfield.

242

There is, up to an isomorphism, at most one algebraic closure of \({\Bbb Q}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
242

There is, up to an isomorphism, at most one algebraic closure of \({\Bbb Q}\).

242

There is, up to an isomorphism, at most one algebraic closure of \({\Bbb Q}\).

243

Every  principal ideal domain is a unique factorization domain.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
243

Every  principal ideal domain is a unique factorization domain.

243

Every  principal ideal domain is a unique factorization domain.

244

Every principal ideal domain has a maximal ideal.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
244

Every principal ideal domain has a maximal ideal.

244

Every principal ideal domain has a maximal ideal.

245

There is a function \(f :\omega_1\rightarrow \omega^{\omega}_1\) such that for every \(\alpha\), \(0 < \alpha < \omega_1\), \(f(\alpha )\) is a function from \(\omega\) onto \(\alpha\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
245

There is a function \(f :\omega_1\rightarrow \omega^{\omega}_1\) such that for every \(\alpha\), \(0 < \alpha < \omega_1\), \(f(\alpha )\) is a function from \(\omega\) onto \(\alpha\).

245

There is a function \(f :\omega_1\rightarrow \omega^{\omega}_1\) such that for every \(\alpha\), \(0 < \alpha < \omega_1\), \(f(\alpha )\) is a function from \(\omega\) onto \(\alpha\).

246

The monadic theory theory \(MT(\omega_1,<)\) of \(\omega_1\) is recursive.  \ac{Litman} \cite{1976} and note 85.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
246

The monadic theory theory \(MT(\omega_1,<)\) of \(\omega_1\) is recursive.  \ac{Litman} \cite{1976} and note 85.

246

The monadic theory theory \(MT(\omega_1,<)\) of \(\omega_1\) is recursive.  \ac{Litman} \cite{1976} and note 85.

247

Every atomless Boolean algebra is Dedekind infinite.  \ac{Plotkin} \cite{1976}, notes 86 and 94.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
247

Every atomless Boolean algebra is Dedekind infinite.  \ac{Plotkin} \cite{1976}, notes 86 and 94.

247

Every atomless Boolean algebra is Dedekind infinite.  \ac{Plotkin} \cite{1976}, notes 86 and 94.

248

For any \(\kappa\), \(\kappa\) is the cardinal number of an infinite complete Boolean algebra if and only if \(\kappa^{\aleph_0} = \kappa \).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
248

For any \(\kappa\), \(\kappa\) is the cardinal number of an infinite complete Boolean algebra if and only if \(\kappa^{\aleph_0} = \kappa \).

248

For any \(\kappa\), \(\kappa\) is the cardinal number of an infinite complete Boolean algebra if and only if \(\kappa^{\aleph_0} = \kappa \).

249

If \(T\) is an infinite tree in which every element has exactly 2 immediate successors then \(T\) has an infinite branch.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
249

If \(T\) is an infinite tree in which every element has exactly 2 immediate successors then \(T\) has an infinite branch.

249

If \(T\) is an infinite tree in which every element has exactly 2 immediate successors then \(T\) has an infinite branch.

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

250

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

251

The additive groups \(({\Bbb R},+)\) and \(({\Bbb C},+)\) are  isomorphic.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
251

The additive groups \(({\Bbb R},+)\) and \(({\Bbb C},+)\) are  isomorphic.

251

The additive groups \(({\Bbb R},+)\) and \(({\Bbb C},+)\) are  isomorphic.

252

The additive groups of \(\Bbb Q\oplus\Bbb R\) and \(\Bbb R\) are isomorphic.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
252

The additive groups of \(\Bbb Q\oplus\Bbb R\) and \(\Bbb R\) are isomorphic.

252

The additive groups of \(\Bbb Q\oplus\Bbb R\) and \(\Bbb R\) are isomorphic.

253

\L o\'s' Theorem: If \(M=\langle A,R_j\rangle_{j\in J}\) is a relational system, \(X\) any set and \({\cal F}\) an ultrafilter in \({\cal P}(X)\), then \(M\) and \(M^{X}/{\cal F}\) are elementarily equivalent.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
253

\L o\'s' Theorem: If \(M=\langle A,R_j\rangle_{j\in J}\) is a relational system, \(X\) any set and \({\cal F}\) an ultrafilter in \({\cal P}(X)\), then \(M\) and \(M^{X}/{\cal F}\) are elementarily equivalent.

253

\L o\'s' Theorem: If \(M=\langle A,R_j\rangle_{j\in J}\) is a relational system, \(X\) any set and \({\cal F}\) an ultrafilter in \({\cal P}(X)\), then \(M\) and \(M^{X}/{\cal F}\) are elementarily equivalent.

254

\(Z(D,R,l)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which ramified subsets have least upper bounds, has a maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
254

\(Z(D,R,l)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which ramified subsets have least upper bounds, has a maximal element.

254

\(Z(D,R,l)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which ramified subsets have least upper bounds, has a maximal element.

255

\(Z(D,R)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
255

\(Z(D,R)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

255

\(Z(D,R)\): Every directed relation \((P,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

256

\(Z(P,F)\): Every partially ordered set \((X,R)\) in which every forest \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
256

\(Z(P,F)\): Every partially ordered set \((X,R)\) in which every forest \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

256

\(Z(P,F)\): Every partially ordered set \((X,R)\) in which every forest \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

257

\(Z(TR,P)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which  every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
257

\(Z(TR,P)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which  every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

257

\(Z(TR,P)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which  every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

258

\(Z(D,L)\): Every directed relation \((X,R)\) in which linearly ordered subsets have upper bounds, has a maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
258

\(Z(D,L)\): Every directed relation \((X,R)\) in which linearly ordered subsets have upper bounds, has a maximal element.

258

\(Z(D,L)\): Every directed relation \((X,R)\) in which linearly ordered subsets have upper bounds, has a maximal element.

259

\(Z(TR\&C,W)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every well ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
259

\(Z(TR\&C,W)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every well ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

259

\(Z(TR\&C,W)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every well ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

260

\(Z(TR\&C,P)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
260

\(Z(TR\&C,P)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

260

\(Z(TR\&C,P)\): If \((X,R)\) is a transitive and connected relation in which every partially ordered subset has an upper bound, then \((X,R)\) has a maximal element.

261

\(Z(TR,T)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every subset which is a tree has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
261

\(Z(TR,T)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every subset which is a tree has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

261

\(Z(TR,T)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every subset which is a tree has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

262

\(Z(TR,R)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
262

\(Z(TR,R)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

262

\(Z(TR,R)\): Every transitive relation \((X,R)\) in which every ramified subset \(A\) has an upper bound, has a maximal element.

263

\(H(AS\&C,P)\): Every every relation \((X,R)\) which is antisymmetric and connected contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
263

\(H(AS\&C,P)\): Every every relation \((X,R)\) which is antisymmetric and connected contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

263

\(H(AS\&C,P)\): Every every relation \((X,R)\) which is antisymmetric and connected contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

264

\(H(C,P)\): Every connected relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered set.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
264

\(H(C,P)\): Every connected relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered set.

264

\(H(C,P)\): Every connected relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered set.

265

\(H(A,TR)\): Every relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
265

\(H(A,TR)\): Every relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

265

\(H(A,TR)\): Every relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal transitive subset.

266

\(H(AS,P)\): Every antisymmetric relation contains \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
266

\(H(AS,P)\): Every antisymmetric relation contains \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

266

\(H(AS,P)\): Every antisymmetric relation contains \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered subset.

267

There is no infinite, free complete Boolean algebra.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
267

There is no infinite, free complete Boolean algebra.

267

There is no infinite, free complete Boolean algebra.

268

If \({\cal L}\)  is  a  lattice  isomorphic  to the  lattice  of subalgebras of some unary universal algebra (a unary universal algebra is one with only unary or nullary operations) and \(\alpha \) is an automorphism of \({\cal L}\) of order 2 (that is, \(\alpha ^{2}\)  is  the  identity) then there is a unary algebra \(\frak A\)  and an isomorphism \(\rho \) from \({\cal L}\) onto the lattice of subalgebras of \(\frak A^{2}\) with \[\rho(\alpha(x))=(\rho(x))^{-1} (= \{(s,t) : (t,s)\in\rho(x)\})\] for all \(x\in  {\cal L}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
268

If \({\cal L}\)  is  a  lattice  isomorphic  to the  lattice  of subalgebras of some unary universal algebra (a unary universal algebra is one with only unary or nullary operations) and \(\alpha \) is an automorphism of \({\cal L}\) of order 2 (that is, \(\alpha ^{2}\)  is  the  identity) then there is a unary algebra \(\frak A\)  and an isomorphism \(\rho \) from \({\cal L}\) onto the lattice of subalgebras of \(\frak A^{2}\) with \[\rho(\alpha(x))=(\rho(x))^{-1} (= \{(s,t) : (t,s)\in\rho(x)\})\] for all \(x\in  {\cal L}\).

268

If \({\cal L}\)  is  a  lattice  isomorphic  to the  lattice  of subalgebras of some unary universal algebra (a unary universal algebra is one with only unary or nullary operations) and \(\alpha \) is an automorphism of \({\cal L}\) of order 2 (that is, \(\alpha ^{2}\)  is  the  identity) then there is a unary algebra \(\frak A\)  and an isomorphism \(\rho \) from \({\cal L}\) onto the lattice of subalgebras of \(\frak A^{2}\) with \[\rho(\alpha(x))=(\rho(x))^{-1} (= \{(s,t) : (t,s)\in\rho(x)\})\] for all \(x\in  {\cal L}\).

269

For every cardinal \(m\), there is a set \(A\) such that \(2^{|A|^2}\ge m\) and there is a choice function on the collection of 2-element subsets of \(A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
269

For every cardinal \(m\), there is a set \(A\) such that \(2^{|A|^2}\ge m\) and there is a choice function on the collection of 2-element subsets of \(A\).

269

For every cardinal \(m\), there is a set \(A\) such that \(2^{|A|^2}\ge m\) and there is a choice function on the collection of 2-element subsets of \(A\).

270

\(CT_{\hbox{fin}}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs only in a finite number of formulas.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
270

\(CT_{\hbox{fin}}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs only in a finite number of formulas.

270

\(CT_{\hbox{fin}}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs only in a finite number of formulas.

271-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(CT_{n}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs in at most \(n\) formulas.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
271-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(CT_{n}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs in at most \(n\) formulas.

271-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(CT_{n}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs in at most \(n\) formulas.

272

There is an \(X\subseteq{\Bbb R}\) such that neither \(X\) nor \(\Bbb R - X\) has a perfect subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
272

There is an \(X\subseteq{\Bbb R}\) such that neither \(X\) nor \(\Bbb R - X\) has a perfect subset.

272

There is an \(X\subseteq{\Bbb R}\) such that neither \(X\) nor \(\Bbb R - X\) has a perfect subset.

273

There is a subset of \({\Bbb R}\) which is not Borel.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
273

There is a subset of \({\Bbb R}\) which is not Borel.

273

There is a subset of \({\Bbb R}\) which is not Borel.

274

There is a cardinal number \(x\) and an \(n\in\omega\) such that \(\neg(x\) adj\(^n\, x^2)\). (The expression ``\(x\) adj\(^n\, ya\)" means there are cardinals \(z_0,\ldots, z_n\) such that \(z_0 = x\) and \(z_n = y\) and for all \(i,\ 0\le i < n,\ z_i< z_{i+1}\) and if  \(z_i < z\le z_{i+1}\), then \(z = z_{i+1}.)\) (Compare with [0 A]).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
274

There is a cardinal number \(x\) and an \(n\in\omega\) such that \(\neg(x\) adj\(^n\, x^2)\). (The expression ``\(x\) adj\(^n\, ya\)" means there are cardinals \(z_0,\ldots, z_n\) such that \(z_0 = x\) and \(z_n = y\) and for all \(i,\ 0\le i < n,\ z_i< z_{i+1}\) and if  \(z_i < z\le z_{i+1}\), then \(z = z_{i+1}.)\) (Compare with [0 A]).

274

There is a cardinal number \(x\) and an \(n\in\omega\) such that \(\neg(x\) adj\(^n\, x^2)\). (The expression ``\(x\) adj\(^n\, ya\)" means there are cardinals \(z_0,\ldots, z_n\) such that \(z_0 = x\) and \(z_n = y\) and for all \(i,\ 0\le i < n,\ z_i< z_{i+1}\) and if  \(z_i < z\le z_{i+1}\), then \(z = z_{i+1}.)\) (Compare with [0 A]).

275

The sequence of cardinals \(\langle\aleph_n: n \in\omega\rangle\) has a unique minimal upper bound.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
275

The sequence of cardinals \(\langle\aleph_n: n \in\omega\rangle\) has a unique minimal upper bound.

275

The sequence of cardinals \(\langle\aleph_n: n \in\omega\rangle\) has a unique minimal upper bound.

276

\(E(V'',III)\): For every set \(A\), \({\cal P}(A)\) is Dedekind finite if and only if \(A = \emptyset\)  or \(2|{\cal P}(A)| > |{\cal P}(A)|\). \ac{Howard/Spi\u siak} \cite{1994}.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
276

\(E(V'',III)\): For every set \(A\), \({\cal P}(A)\) is Dedekind finite if and only if \(A = \emptyset\)  or \(2|{\cal P}(A)| > |{\cal P}(A)|\). \ac{Howard/Spi\u siak} \cite{1994}.

276

\(E(V'',III)\): For every set \(A\), \({\cal P}(A)\) is Dedekind finite if and only if \(A = \emptyset\)  or \(2|{\cal P}(A)| > |{\cal P}(A)|\). \ac{Howard/Spi\u siak} \cite{1994}.

277

\(E(D,VII)\): Every non-well-orderable cardinal is decomposable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
277

\(E(D,VII)\): Every non-well-orderable cardinal is decomposable.

277

\(E(D,VII)\): Every non-well-orderable cardinal is decomposable.

278

In an integral domain \(R\), if every ideal is finitely generated then \(R\) has a maximal proper ideal. note 45 E.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
278

In an integral domain \(R\), if every ideal is finitely generated then \(R\) has a maximal proper ideal. note 45 E.

278

In an integral domain \(R\), if every ideal is finitely generated then \(R\) has a maximal proper ideal. note 45 E.

279

The Closed Graph Theorem for operations between Fréchet Spaces: Suppose \(X\) and \(Y\) are Fréchet spaces, \(T:X\to Y\) is linear and \(G=\{(x,Tx): x \in X \}\) is closed in \(X\times Y\). Then \(T\) is continuous. Rudin [1991] p. 51.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
279

The Closed Graph Theorem for operations between Fréchet Spaces: Suppose \(X\) and \(Y\) are Fréchet spaces, \(T:X\to Y\) is linear and \(G=\{(x,Tx): x \in X \}\) is closed in \(X\times Y\). Then \(T\) is continuous. Rudin [1991] p. 51.

279

The Closed Graph Theorem for operations between Fréchet Spaces: Suppose \(X\) and \(Y\) are Fréchet spaces, \(T:X\to Y\) is linear and \(G=\{(x,Tx): x \in X \}\) is closed in \(X\times Y\). Then \(T\) is continuous. Rudin [1991] p. 51.

280

There is a complete separable metric space with a subset which does not have the Baire property.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
280

There is a complete separable metric space with a subset which does not have the Baire property.

280

There is a complete separable metric space with a subset which does not have the Baire property.

281

There is a Hilbert space \(H\) and an  unbounded linear operator on \(H\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
281

There is a Hilbert space \(H\) and an  unbounded linear operator on \(H\).

281

There is a Hilbert space \(H\) and an  unbounded linear operator on \(H\).

282

\(\omega\not\to(\omega)^{\omega}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
282

\(\omega\not\to(\omega)^{\omega}\).

282

\(\omega\not\to(\omega)^{\omega}\).

283

Cardinality of well ordered subsets:  For all \(n\in\omega\) and for all infinite \(x\), \(|x^n| < |s(x)|\) where \(s(x)\) is the set of all well orderable subsets of \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
283

Cardinality of well ordered subsets:  For all \(n\in\omega\) and for all infinite \(x\), \(|x^n| < |s(x)|\) where \(s(x)\) is the set of all well orderable subsets of \(x\).

283

Cardinality of well ordered subsets:  For all \(n\in\omega\) and for all infinite \(x\), \(|x^n| < |s(x)|\) where \(s(x)\) is the set of all well orderable subsets of \(x\).

284

A system of linear equations over a field \(F\) has a solution in \(F\) if and only if every finite sub-system has a solution in \(F\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
284

A system of linear equations over a field \(F\) has a solution in \(F\) if and only if every finite sub-system has a solution in \(F\).

284

A system of linear equations over a field \(F\) has a solution in \(F\) if and only if every finite sub-system has a solution in \(F\).

285

Let \(E\) be a set and \(f: E\to E\), then \(f\) has a fixed point if and only if \(E\) is not the union of three mutually disjoint sets \(E_1\), \(E_2\) and \(E_3\) such that \(E_i \cap f(E_i) = \emptyset\) for \(i=1, 2, 3\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
285

Let \(E\) be a set and \(f: E\to E\), then \(f\) has a fixed point if and only if \(E\) is not the union of three mutually disjoint sets \(E_1\), \(E_2\) and \(E_3\) such that \(E_i \cap f(E_i) = \emptyset\) for \(i=1, 2, 3\).

285

Let \(E\) be a set and \(f: E\to E\), then \(f\) has a fixed point if and only if \(E\) is not the union of three mutually disjoint sets \(E_1\), \(E_2\) and \(E_3\) such that \(E_i \cap f(E_i) = \emptyset\) for \(i=1, 2, 3\).

286

Extended Krein-Milman Theorem:  Let K be a quasicompact (sometimes called convex-compact), convex subset of a locally convex topological vector space, then K has an extreme point. H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], p. 177-178.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
286

Extended Krein-Milman Theorem:  Let K be a quasicompact (sometimes called convex-compact), convex subset of a locally convex topological vector space, then K has an extreme point. H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], p. 177-178.

286

Extended Krein-Milman Theorem:  Let K be a quasicompact (sometimes called convex-compact), convex subset of a locally convex topological vector space, then K has an extreme point. H. Rubin/J. Rubin [1985], p. 177-178.

287

The Hahn-Banach Theorem for Separable Normed Linear Spaces:  Assume \(V\) is a separable normed linear space and \(p :V \to \Bbb R\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t \ge 0)(\forall x \in V)(p(tx) = tp(x))\) and assume \(f\) is a linear function from a subspace \(S\) of \(V\) into \(\Bbb R\) which satisfies \((\forall x \in S)(f(x) \le p(x))\), then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^* :V \to \Bbb R\) so that \(f^* \) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^*(x) \le p(x))\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
287

The Hahn-Banach Theorem for Separable Normed Linear Spaces:  Assume \(V\) is a separable normed linear space and \(p :V \to \Bbb R\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t \ge 0)(\forall x \in V)(p(tx) = tp(x))\) and assume \(f\) is a linear function from a subspace \(S\) of \(V\) into \(\Bbb R\) which satisfies \((\forall x \in S)(f(x) \le p(x))\), then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^* :V \to \Bbb R\) so that \(f^* \) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^*(x) \le p(x))\).

287

The Hahn-Banach Theorem for Separable Normed Linear Spaces:  Assume \(V\) is a separable normed linear space and \(p :V \to \Bbb R\) satisfies \(p(x+y) \le p(x) + p(y)\) and \((\forall t \ge 0)(\forall x \in V)(p(tx) = tp(x))\) and assume \(f\) is a linear function from a subspace \(S\) of \(V\) into \(\Bbb R\) which satisfies \((\forall x \in S)(f(x) \le p(x))\), then \(f\) can be extended to \(f^* :V \to \Bbb R\) so that \(f^* \) is linear and \((\forall x \in V)(f^*(x) \le p(x))\).

288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

288-n

If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0,n)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has a choice function.

289

If \(S\) is a set of subsets of a countable set and \(S\) is closed under chain unions, then \(S\) has a \(\subseteq\)-maximal element.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
289

If \(S\) is a set of subsets of a countable set and \(S\) is closed under chain unions, then \(S\) has a \(\subseteq\)-maximal element.

289

If \(S\) is a set of subsets of a countable set and \(S\) is closed under chain unions, then \(S\) has a \(\subseteq\)-maximal element.

290

For all infinite \(x\), \(|2^x|=|x^x|\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
290

For all infinite \(x\), \(|2^x|=|x^x|\).

290

For all infinite \(x\), \(|2^x|=|x^x|\).

291

For all infinite \(x\), \(|x!|=|x^x|\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
291

For all infinite \(x\), \(|x!|=|x^x|\).

291

For all infinite \(x\), \(|x!|=|x^x|\).

292

\(MC(LO,\infty)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
292

\(MC(LO,\infty)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

292

\(MC(LO,\infty)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

293

For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\) can be linearly ordered and there is a mapping of \(x\) onto \(y\), then \(y\) can be linearly ordered.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
293

For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\) can be linearly ordered and there is a mapping of \(x\) onto \(y\), then \(y\) can be linearly ordered.

293

For all sets \(x\) and \(y\), if \(x\) can be linearly ordered and there is a mapping of \(x\) onto \(y\), then \(y\) can be linearly ordered.

294

Every linearly ordered \(W\)-set is well orderable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
294

Every linearly ordered \(W\)-set is well orderable.

294

Every linearly ordered \(W\)-set is well orderable.

295

DO:  Every infinite set has a dense linear ordering.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
295

DO:  Every infinite set has a dense linear ordering.

295

DO:  Every infinite set has a dense linear ordering.

296

Part-\(\infty\): Every infinite set is the disjoint union of infinitely many infinite sets.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
296

Part-\(\infty\): Every infinite set is the disjoint union of infinitely many infinite sets.

296

Part-\(\infty\): Every infinite set is the disjoint union of infinitely many infinite sets.

297

Extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces are projective in the category of all compact Hausdorff spaces.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
297

Extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces are projective in the category of all compact Hausdorff spaces.

297

Extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces are projective in the category of all compact Hausdorff spaces.

298

Every compact Hausdorff space has a Gleason cover.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
298

Every compact Hausdorff space has a Gleason cover.

298

Every compact Hausdorff space has a Gleason cover.

299

Any extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff space is projective in the category of Boolean topological spaces.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
299

Any extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff space is projective in the category of Boolean topological spaces.

299

Any extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff space is projective in the category of Boolean topological spaces.

300

Any continuous surjection between extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
300

Any continuous surjection between extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

300

Any continuous surjection between extremally disconnected compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

301

Any continuous surjection between Boolean spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
301

Any continuous surjection between Boolean spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

301

Any continuous surjection between Boolean spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

302

Any continuous surjection between compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
302

Any continuous surjection between compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

302

Any continuous surjection between compact Hausdorff spaces has an irreducible restriction to a closed subset of its domain.

303

If \(B\) is a Boolean algebra, \(S\subseteq B\) and \(S\) is closed under \(\land\), then there is a \(\subseteq\)-maximal proper ideal \(I\) of \(B\) such that \(I\cap S= \{0\}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
303

If \(B\) is a Boolean algebra, \(S\subseteq B\) and \(S\) is closed under \(\land\), then there is a \(\subseteq\)-maximal proper ideal \(I\) of \(B\) such that \(I\cap S= \{0\}\).

303

If \(B\) is a Boolean algebra, \(S\subseteq B\) and \(S\) is closed under \(\land\), then there is a \(\subseteq\)-maximal proper ideal \(I\) of \(B\) such that \(I\cap S= \{0\}\).

304

There does not exist a \(T_2\) topological space \(X\) such that every infinite subset of \(X\) contains an infinite compact subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
304

There does not exist a \(T_2\) topological space \(X\) such that every infinite subset of \(X\) contains an infinite compact subset.

304

There does not exist a \(T_2\) topological space \(X\) such that every infinite subset of \(X\) contains an infinite compact subset.

305

There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Vitali equivalence classes. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).). \ac{Kanovei} \cite{1991}.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
305

There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Vitali equivalence classes. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).). \ac{Kanovei} \cite{1991}.

305

There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Vitali equivalence classes. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).). \ac{Kanovei} \cite{1991}.

306

The set of Vitali equivalence classes is linearly orderable. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow (\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y = q)\).).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
306

The set of Vitali equivalence classes is linearly orderable. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow (\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y = q)\).).

306

The set of Vitali equivalence classes is linearly orderable. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow (\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y = q)\).).

307

If \(m\) is the cardinality of the set of Vitali equivalence classes, then \(H(m) = H(2^{\aleph_0})\), where \(H\) is Hartogs aleph function and the {\it Vitali equivalence classes} are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in {\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
307

If \(m\) is the cardinality of the set of Vitali equivalence classes, then \(H(m) = H(2^{\aleph_0})\), where \(H\) is Hartogs aleph function and the {\it Vitali equivalence classes} are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in {\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).

307

If \(m\) is the cardinality of the set of Vitali equivalence classes, then \(H(m) = H(2^{\aleph_0})\), where \(H\) is Hartogs aleph function and the {\it Vitali equivalence classes} are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in {\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).

308-p

If \(p\) is a prime and if \(\{G_y: y\in Y\}\) is a set of finite groups, then the weak direct product \(\prod_{y\in Y}G_y\) has a maximal \(p\)-subgroup.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
308-p

If \(p\) is a prime and if \(\{G_y: y\in Y\}\) is a set of finite groups, then the weak direct product \(\prod_{y\in Y}G_y\) has a maximal \(p\)-subgroup.

308-p

If \(p\) is a prime and if \(\{G_y: y\in Y\}\) is a set of finite groups, then the weak direct product \(\prod_{y\in Y}G_y\) has a maximal \(p\)-subgroup.

309

The Banach-Tarski Paradox: There are three finite partitions \(\{P_1,\ldots\), \(P_n\}\), \(\{Q_1,\ldots,Q_r\}\) and \(\{S_1,\ldots,S_n, T_1,\ldots,T_r\}\) of \(B^3 = \{x\in {\Bbb R}^3 : |x| \le 1\}\) such that \(P_i\) is congruent to \(S_i\) for \(1\le i\le n\) and \(Q_i\) is congruent to \(T_i\) for \(1\le i\le r\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
309

The Banach-Tarski Paradox: There are three finite partitions \(\{P_1,\ldots\), \(P_n\}\), \(\{Q_1,\ldots,Q_r\}\) and \(\{S_1,\ldots,S_n, T_1,\ldots,T_r\}\) of \(B^3 = \{x\in {\Bbb R}^3 : |x| \le 1\}\) such that \(P_i\) is congruent to \(S_i\) for \(1\le i\le n\) and \(Q_i\) is congruent to \(T_i\) for \(1\le i\le r\).

309

The Banach-Tarski Paradox: There are three finite partitions \(\{P_1,\ldots\), \(P_n\}\), \(\{Q_1,\ldots,Q_r\}\) and \(\{S_1,\ldots,S_n, T_1,\ldots,T_r\}\) of \(B^3 = \{x\in {\Bbb R}^3 : |x| \le 1\}\) such that \(P_i\) is congruent to \(S_i\) for \(1\le i\le n\) and \(Q_i\) is congruent to \(T_i\) for \(1\le i\le r\).

310

The Measure Extension Theorem: Suppose that \(\cal A_0\) is a subring (that is, \(a,b \in \cal A_0  \to a\vee b \in \cal A_0\) and \(a-b \in \cal A_0\)) of a Boolean algebra \(\cal A\) and \(\mu\) is a measure on \(\cal A_0\) (that is, \(\mu:\cal A \to [0,\infty]\), \(\mu(a\vee b) =\mu(a)+\mu(b)\) for \(a\land b = 0\), and \(\mu(0) = 0\).) then there is a measure on \(\cal A\) that extends \(\mu\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
310

The Measure Extension Theorem: Suppose that \(\cal A_0\) is a subring (that is, \(a,b \in \cal A_0  \to a\vee b \in \cal A_0\) and \(a-b \in \cal A_0\)) of a Boolean algebra \(\cal A\) and \(\mu\) is a measure on \(\cal A_0\) (that is, \(\mu:\cal A \to [0,\infty]\), \(\mu(a\vee b) =\mu(a)+\mu(b)\) for \(a\land b = 0\), and \(\mu(0) = 0\).) then there is a measure on \(\cal A\) that extends \(\mu\).

310

The Measure Extension Theorem: Suppose that \(\cal A_0\) is a subring (that is, \(a,b \in \cal A_0  \to a\vee b \in \cal A_0\) and \(a-b \in \cal A_0\)) of a Boolean algebra \(\cal A\) and \(\mu\) is a measure on \(\cal A_0\) (that is, \(\mu:\cal A \to [0,\infty]\), \(\mu(a\vee b) =\mu(a)+\mu(b)\) for \(a\land b = 0\), and \(\mu(0) = 0\).) then there is a measure on \(\cal A\) that extends \(\mu\).

311

Abelian groups are amenable. (\(G\) is amenable if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G)=1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
311

Abelian groups are amenable. (\(G\) is amenable if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G)=1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

311

Abelian groups are amenable. (\(G\) is amenable if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G)=1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

312

A subgroup of an amenable group is amenable. (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g \in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
312

A subgroup of an amenable group is amenable. (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g \in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

312

A subgroup of an amenable group is amenable. (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g \in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

313

\(\Bbb Z\) (the set of integers under addition) is amenable.  (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
313

\(\Bbb Z\) (the set of integers under addition) is amenable.  (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

313

\(\Bbb Z\) (the set of integers under addition) is amenable.  (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).)

314

For every set \(X\) and every permutation \(\pi\) on \(X\) there are two reflections \(\rho\) and \(\sigma\) on \(X\) such that \(\pi =\rho\circ\sigma\) and for every \(Y\subseteq X\) if \(\pi[Y]=Y\) then \(\rho[Y]=Y\) and \(\sigma[Y]=Y\).  (A reflection is a permutation \(\phi\) such that \(\phi^2\) is the identity.) \ac{Degen} \cite{1988}, \cite{2000}.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
314

For every set \(X\) and every permutation \(\pi\) on \(X\) there are two reflections \(\rho\) and \(\sigma\) on \(X\) such that \(\pi =\rho\circ\sigma\) and for every \(Y\subseteq X\) if \(\pi[Y]=Y\) then \(\rho[Y]=Y\) and \(\sigma[Y]=Y\).  (A reflection is a permutation \(\phi\) such that \(\phi^2\) is the identity.) \ac{Degen} \cite{1988}, \cite{2000}.

314

For every set \(X\) and every permutation \(\pi\) on \(X\) there are two reflections \(\rho\) and \(\sigma\) on \(X\) such that \(\pi =\rho\circ\sigma\) and for every \(Y\subseteq X\) if \(\pi[Y]=Y\) then \(\rho[Y]=Y\) and \(\sigma[Y]=Y\).  (A reflection is a permutation \(\phi\) such that \(\phi^2\) is the identity.) \ac{Degen} \cite{1988}, \cite{2000}.

315

\(\Omega = \omega_1\), where
\(\Omega = \{\alpha\in\hbox{ On}: (\forall\beta\le\alpha)(\beta=0 \vee (\exists\gamma)(\beta=\gamma+1) \vee\)
there is a sequence \(\langle\gamma_n: n\in\omega\rangle\) such that for each \(n\),
\(\gamma_n<\beta\hbox{ and } \beta=\bigcup_{n<\omega}\gamma_n.)\} \)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
315

\(\Omega = \omega_1\), where
\(\Omega = \{\alpha\in\hbox{ On}: (\forall\beta\le\alpha)(\beta=0 \vee (\exists\gamma)(\beta=\gamma+1) \vee\)
there is a sequence \(\langle\gamma_n: n\in\omega\rangle\) such that for each \(n\),
\(\gamma_n<\beta\hbox{ and } \beta=\bigcup_{n<\omega}\gamma_n.)\} \)

315

\(\Omega = \omega_1\), where
\(\Omega = \{\alpha\in\hbox{ On}: (\forall\beta\le\alpha)(\beta=0 \vee (\exists\gamma)(\beta=\gamma+1) \vee\)
there is a sequence \(\langle\gamma_n: n\in\omega\rangle\) such that for each \(n\),
\(\gamma_n<\beta\hbox{ and } \beta=\bigcup_{n<\omega}\gamma_n.)\} \)

316

If a linearly ordered set \((A,\le)\) has the fixed point property then \((A,\le)\) is complete. (\((A,\le)\)  has the fixed point property if every function \(f:A\to A\) satisfying \((x\le y \Rightarrow f(x)\le f(y))\) has a fixed point, and (\((A,\le)\) is complete if every subset of \(A\) has a least upper bound.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
316

If a linearly ordered set \((A,\le)\) has the fixed point property then \((A,\le)\) is complete. (\((A,\le)\)  has the fixed point property if every function \(f:A\to A\) satisfying \((x\le y \Rightarrow f(x)\le f(y))\) has a fixed point, and (\((A,\le)\) is complete if every subset of \(A\) has a least upper bound.)

316

If a linearly ordered set \((A,\le)\) has the fixed point property then \((A,\le)\) is complete. (\((A,\le)\)  has the fixed point property if every function \(f:A\to A\) satisfying \((x\le y \Rightarrow f(x)\le f(y))\) has a fixed point, and (\((A,\le)\) is complete if every subset of \(A\) has a least upper bound.)

317

Weak Sikorski Theorem:  If \(B\) is a complete, well orderable Boolean algebra and \(f\) is a homomorphism of the Boolean algebra \(A'\) into \(B\) where \(A'\) is a subalgebra of the Boolean algebra \(A\), then \(f\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
317

Weak Sikorski Theorem:  If \(B\) is a complete, well orderable Boolean algebra and \(f\) is a homomorphism of the Boolean algebra \(A'\) into \(B\) where \(A'\) is a subalgebra of the Boolean algebra \(A\), then \(f\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B\).

317

Weak Sikorski Theorem:  If \(B\) is a complete, well orderable Boolean algebra and \(f\) is a homomorphism of the Boolean algebra \(A'\) into \(B\) where \(A'\) is a subalgebra of the Boolean algebra \(A\), then \(f\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B\).

318

\(\aleph_1\) is not measurable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
318

\(\aleph_1\) is not measurable.

318

\(\aleph_1\) is not measurable.

319

Measurable cardinals are inaccessible.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
319

Measurable cardinals are inaccessible.

319

Measurable cardinals are inaccessible.

320

No successor cardinal, \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\), is measurable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
320

No successor cardinal, \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\), is measurable.

320

No successor cardinal, \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\), is measurable.

321

There does not exist an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) is weakly compact and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) is measurable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
321

There does not exist an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) is weakly compact and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) is measurable.

321

There does not exist an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) is weakly compact and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) is measurable.

322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

323

\(KW(\infty,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of well orderable sets: For every set \(M\) of well orderable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15.)

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

324

\(KW(WO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of well orderable sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of well orderable sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

325

Ramsey's Theorem II: \(\forall n,m\in\omega\), if A is an infinite set and the family of all \(m\) element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into \(n\) sets \(S_{j}, 1\le j\le n\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all \(m\) element subsets of \(B\) belong to the same \(S_{j}\). (Also, see Form 17.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
325

Ramsey's Theorem II: \(\forall n,m\in\omega\), if A is an infinite set and the family of all \(m\) element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into \(n\) sets \(S_{j}, 1\le j\le n\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all \(m\) element subsets of \(B\) belong to the same \(S_{j}\). (Also, see Form 17.)

325

Ramsey's Theorem II: \(\forall n,m\in\omega\), if A is an infinite set and the family of all \(m\) element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into \(n\) sets \(S_{j}, 1\le j\le n\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all \(m\) element subsets of \(B\) belong to the same \(S_{j}\). (Also, see Form 17.)

326

2-SAT:  Restricted Compactness Theorem for Propositional Logic III:   If \(\Sigma\) is a set of formulas in a propositional language such that every finite subset of \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable and if every formula in \(\Sigma\) is a disjunction of at most two literals, then \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable. (A literal is a propositional variable or its negation.) Wojtylak [1999] (listed as Wojtylak [1995])

0
 \(0 = 0\).
326

2-SAT:  Restricted Compactness Theorem for Propositional Logic III:   If \(\Sigma\) is a set of formulas in a propositional language such that every finite subset of \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable and if every formula in \(\Sigma\) is a disjunction of at most two literals, then \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable. (A literal is a propositional variable or its negation.) Wojtylak [1999] (listed as Wojtylak [1995])

326

2-SAT:  Restricted Compactness Theorem for Propositional Logic III:   If \(\Sigma\) is a set of formulas in a propositional language such that every finite subset of \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable and if every formula in \(\Sigma\) is a disjunction of at most two literals, then \(\Sigma\) is satisfiable. (A literal is a propositional variable or its negation.) Wojtylak [1999] (listed as Wojtylak [1995])

327

\(KW(WO,<\aleph_0)\),  The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of finite sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
327

\(KW(WO,<\aleph_0)\),  The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of finite sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

327

\(KW(WO,<\aleph_0)\),  The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of finite sets: For every well ordered set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 15.)

328

\(MC(WO,\infty)\): For  every well ordered set \(X\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that and for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\). (See Form 67.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
328

\(MC(WO,\infty)\): For  every well ordered set \(X\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that and for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\). (See Form 67.)

328

\(MC(WO,\infty)\): For  every well ordered set \(X\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that and for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\). (See Form 67.)

329

\(MC(\infty,WO)\): For  every set \(M\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
329

\(MC(\infty,WO)\): For  every set \(M\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

329

\(MC(\infty,WO)\): For  every set \(M\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

330

\(MC(WO,WO)\): For every well ordered set \(X\) of well orderable sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).  (See Form 67.)

331

If \((X_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of compact non-empty topological spaces then there is a family \((F_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(F_i\) is an irreducible closed subset of \(X_i\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
331

If \((X_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of compact non-empty topological spaces then there is a family \((F_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(F_i\) is an irreducible closed subset of \(X_i\).

331

If \((X_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of compact non-empty topological spaces then there is a family \((F_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(F_i\) is an irreducible closed subset of \(X_i\).

332
 

A product of non-empty compact sober topological spaces is non-empty.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
332
 

A product of non-empty compact sober topological spaces is non-empty.

332
 

A product of non-empty compact sober topological spaces is non-empty.

333

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
333

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

333

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

334

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\hbox{ even})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is even.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
334

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\hbox{ even})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is even.

334

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\hbox{ even})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is even.

335-n

Every quotient group of an Abelian group each of whose elements has order  \(\le n\) has a set of representatives.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
335-n

Every quotient group of an Abelian group each of whose elements has order  \(\le n\) has a set of representatives.

335-n

Every quotient group of an Abelian group each of whose elements has order  \(\le n\) has a set of representatives.

336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

336-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).)  For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

337

\(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered):  If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
337

\(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered):  If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\).

337

\(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered):  If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\).

338

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,WO)\): The union of a denumerable number of denumerable sets is well orderable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
338

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,WO)\): The union of a denumerable number of denumerable sets is well orderable.

338

\(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,WO)\): The union of a denumerable number of denumerable sets is well orderable.

339

Martin's Axiom \((\aleph_{0})\): Whenever \((P\le)\) is a non-empty, ccc  quasi-order (ccc means every anti-chain is countable) and \({\cal D}\) is a family of \(\le\aleph_0\) dense subsets of \(P\), then there is a \({\cal D}\) generic filter \(G\) in \(P\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
339

Martin's Axiom \((\aleph_{0})\): Whenever \((P\le)\) is a non-empty, ccc  quasi-order (ccc means every anti-chain is countable) and \({\cal D}\) is a family of \(\le\aleph_0\) dense subsets of \(P\), then there is a \({\cal D}\) generic filter \(G\) in \(P\).

339

Martin's Axiom \((\aleph_{0})\): Whenever \((P\le)\) is a non-empty, ccc  quasi-order (ccc means every anti-chain is countable) and \({\cal D}\) is a family of \(\le\aleph_0\) dense subsets of \(P\), then there is a \({\cal D}\) generic filter \(G\) in \(P\).

340

Every Lindelöf metric space is separable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
340

Every Lindelöf metric space is separable.

340

Every Lindelöf metric space is separable.

341

Every Lindelöf metric space is second countable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
341

Every Lindelöf metric space is second countable.

341

Every Lindelöf metric space is second countable.

342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

342-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\infty,n,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. (See Form 166.)

343

A product of non-empty, compact \(T_2\) topological spaces is non-empty.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
343

A product of non-empty, compact \(T_2\) topological spaces is non-empty.

343

A product of non-empty, compact \(T_2\) topological spaces is non-empty.

344

If \((E_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of non-empty sets, then there is a family \((U_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(U_i\) is an ultrafilter on \(E_i\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
344

If \((E_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of non-empty sets, then there is a family \((U_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(U_i\) is an ultrafilter on \(E_i\).

344

If \((E_i)_{i\in I}\) is a family of non-empty sets, then there is a family \((U_i)_{i\in I}\) such that \(\forall i\in I\), \(U_i\) is an ultrafilter on \(E_i\).

345

Rasiowa-Sikorski Axiom:  If \((B,\land,\lor)\) is a Boolean algebra, \(a\) is a non-zero element of \(B\), and \(\{X_n: n\in\omega\}\) is a denumerable set of subsets of \(B\) then there is a maximal filter \(F\) of \(B\) such that \(a\in F\) and for each \(n\in\omega\), if \(X_n\subseteq F\) and \(\bigwedge X_n\) exists then \(\bigwedge X_n \in F\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
345

Rasiowa-Sikorski Axiom:  If \((B,\land,\lor)\) is a Boolean algebra, \(a\) is a non-zero element of \(B\), and \(\{X_n: n\in\omega\}\) is a denumerable set of subsets of \(B\) then there is a maximal filter \(F\) of \(B\) such that \(a\in F\) and for each \(n\in\omega\), if \(X_n\subseteq F\) and \(\bigwedge X_n\) exists then \(\bigwedge X_n \in F\).

345

Rasiowa-Sikorski Axiom:  If \((B,\land,\lor)\) is a Boolean algebra, \(a\) is a non-zero element of \(B\), and \(\{X_n: n\in\omega\}\) is a denumerable set of subsets of \(B\) then there is a maximal filter \(F\) of \(B\) such that \(a\in F\) and for each \(n\in\omega\), if \(X_n\subseteq F\) and \(\bigwedge X_n\) exists then \(\bigwedge X_n \in F\).

346

If \(V\) is a vector space without a finite basis then \(V\) contains an infinite, well ordered, linearly independent subset.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
346

If \(V\) is a vector space without a finite basis then \(V\) contains an infinite, well ordered, linearly independent subset.

346

If \(V\) is a vector space without a finite basis then \(V\) contains an infinite, well ordered, linearly independent subset.

347

Idemmultiple Partition Principle: If \(y\) is idemmultiple (\(2\times y\approx y\)) and \(x\precsim ^* y\), then \(x\precsim y\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
347

Idemmultiple Partition Principle: If \(y\) is idemmultiple (\(2\times y\approx y\)) and \(x\precsim ^* y\), then \(x\precsim y\).

347

Idemmultiple Partition Principle: If \(y\) is idemmultiple (\(2\times y\approx y\)) and \(x\precsim ^* y\), then \(x\precsim y\).

348

If \(G\) is a group and \(X\) and \(Y\) both freely generate \(G\) then \(|X| = |Y|\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
348

If \(G\) is a group and \(X\) and \(Y\) both freely generate \(G\) then \(|X| = |Y|\).

348

If \(G\) is a group and \(X\) and \(Y\) both freely generate \(G\) then \(|X| = |Y|\).

349

\(MC(\infty,\aleph_0)\): For every set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
349

\(MC(\infty,\aleph_0)\): For every set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

349

\(MC(\infty,\aleph_0)\): For every set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

350

\(MC(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\): For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\).

351

A countable product of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
351

A countable product of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

351

A countable product of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

352

A countable product of second countable spaces is second countable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
352

A countable product of second countable spaces is second countable.

352

A countable product of second countable spaces is second countable.

353

A countable product of first countable spaces is first countable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
353

A countable product of first countable spaces is first countable.

353

A countable product of first countable spaces is first countable.

354

A countable product of separable \(T_2\) spaces is separable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
354

A countable product of separable \(T_2\) spaces is separable.

354

A countable product of separable \(T_2\) spaces is separable.

355

\(KW(\aleph_0,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
355

\(KW(\aleph_0,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

355

\(KW(\aleph_0,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

356

  \(KW(\infty,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of denumerable sets: For every set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
356

  \(KW(\infty,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of denumerable sets: For every set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

356

  \(KW(\infty,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a family of denumerable sets: For every set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\)  then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

357

\(KW(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of denumerable sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
357

\(KW(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of denumerable sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

357

\(KW(\aleph_0,\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of denumerable sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of denumerable sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

358

\(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
358

\(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

358

\(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

359

If \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| \le |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| \le |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
359

If \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| \le |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| \le |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\).

359

If \(\{A_{x}: x\in S\}\) and \(\{B_{x}: x\in S\}\) are families  of pairwise disjoint sets and \( |A_{x}| \le |B_{x}|\) for all \(x\in S\), then \(|\bigcup_{x\in S}A_{x}| \le |\bigcup_{x\in S} B_{x}|\).

360

A system of linear equations over the field \(\{0,1\}\) has a solution, if and only if every finite subsystem has a solution. Brunner [2001]

0
 \(0 = 0\).
360

A system of linear equations over the field \(\{0,1\}\) has a solution, if and only if every finite subsystem has a solution. Brunner [2001]

360

A system of linear equations over the field \(\{0,1\}\) has a solution, if and only if every finite subsystem has a solution. Brunner [2001]

361

In \(\Bbb R\), the union of a denumerable number of analytic sets is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
361

In \(\Bbb R\), the union of a denumerable number of analytic sets is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

361

In \(\Bbb R\), the union of a denumerable number of analytic sets is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

362

In \(\Bbb R\), every Borel set is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
362

In \(\Bbb R\), every Borel set is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

362

In \(\Bbb R\), every Borel set is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325.

363

There are exactly \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Borel sets in \(\Bbb R\). G. Moore [1982], p 325.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
363

There are exactly \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Borel sets in \(\Bbb R\). G. Moore [1982], p 325.

363

There are exactly \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Borel sets in \(\Bbb R\). G. Moore [1982], p 325.

364

In \(\Bbb R\), there is a measurable set that is not Borel.  G. Moore [1982], p 325.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
364

In \(\Bbb R\), there is a measurable set that is not Borel.  G. Moore [1982], p 325.

364

In \(\Bbb R\), there is a measurable set that is not Borel.  G. Moore [1982], p 325.

365

For every uncountable set \(A\), if \(A\) has the same cardinality as each of its uncountable subsets then \(|A| = \aleph_1\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
365

For every uncountable set \(A\), if \(A\) has the same cardinality as each of its uncountable subsets then \(|A| = \aleph_1\).

365

For every uncountable set \(A\), if \(A\) has the same cardinality as each of its uncountable subsets then \(|A| = \aleph_1\).

366

There is a discontinuous function \(f: \Bbb R \to\Bbb R\) such that for all real \(x\) and \(y\), \(f(x+y)=f(x)+f(y)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
366

There is a discontinuous function \(f: \Bbb R \to\Bbb R\) such that for all real \(x\) and \(y\), \(f(x+y)=f(x)+f(y)\).

366

There is a discontinuous function \(f: \Bbb R \to\Bbb R\) such that for all real \(x\) and \(y\), \(f(x+y)=f(x)+f(y)\).

367

There is a Hamel basis for \(\Bbb R\) as a vector space over \(\Bbb Q\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
367

There is a Hamel basis for \(\Bbb R\) as a vector space over \(\Bbb Q\).

367

There is a Hamel basis for \(\Bbb R\) as a vector space over \(\Bbb Q\).

368

The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
368

The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

368

The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

369

If \(\Bbb R\) is partitioned into two sets, at least one of them has cardinality \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
369

If \(\Bbb R\) is partitioned into two sets, at least one of them has cardinality \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

369

If \(\Bbb R\) is partitioned into two sets, at least one of them has cardinality \(2^{\aleph_0}\).

370

Weak Gelfand Extreme Point Theorem: If \(A\) is a non-trivial Gelfand algebra then the closed unit ball in the dual of \(A\) has an extreme point \(e\).  Morillon [1986].

0
 \(0 = 0\).
370

Weak Gelfand Extreme Point Theorem: If \(A\) is a non-trivial Gelfand algebra then the closed unit ball in the dual of \(A\) has an extreme point \(e\).  Morillon [1986].

370

Weak Gelfand Extreme Point Theorem: If \(A\) is a non-trivial Gelfand algebra then the closed unit ball in the dual of \(A\) has an extreme point \(e\).  Morillon [1986].

371

There is an infinite, compact, Hausdorff, extremally disconnected topological space.  Morillon [1993].

0
 \(0 = 0\).
371

There is an infinite, compact, Hausdorff, extremally disconnected topological space.  Morillon [1993].

371

There is an infinite, compact, Hausdorff, extremally disconnected topological space.  Morillon [1993].

372

Generalized Hahn-Banach Theorem:  Assume that \(X\) is a real vector space, \((Z,\preccurlyeq)\) is a Dedekind complete ordered vector space and \(X_0\) is a subspace of \(X\).  If \(\lambda_0 : X_0 \to Z\) is linear and \(p: X\to Z\) is sublinear and if \(\lambda_0 \preccurlyeq p\) on \(X_0\) then \(\lambda_0\) can be extended to a linear map \(\lambda : X\to Z\) such that \(\lambda \preccurlyeq p\) on \(X\). \ac{Schechter} \cite{1996b}

0
 \(0 = 0\).
372

Generalized Hahn-Banach Theorem:  Assume that \(X\) is a real vector space, \((Z,\preccurlyeq)\) is a Dedekind complete ordered vector space and \(X_0\) is a subspace of \(X\).  If \(\lambda_0 : X_0 \to Z\) is linear and \(p: X\to Z\) is sublinear and if \(\lambda_0 \preccurlyeq p\) on \(X_0\) then \(\lambda_0\) can be extended to a linear map \(\lambda : X\to Z\) such that \(\lambda \preccurlyeq p\) on \(X\). \ac{Schechter} \cite{1996b}

372

Generalized Hahn-Banach Theorem:  Assume that \(X\) is a real vector space, \((Z,\preccurlyeq)\) is a Dedekind complete ordered vector space and \(X_0\) is a subspace of \(X\).  If \(\lambda_0 : X_0 \to Z\) is linear and \(p: X\to Z\) is sublinear and if \(\lambda_0 \preccurlyeq p\) on \(X_0\) then \(\lambda_0\) can be extended to a linear map \(\lambda : X\to Z\) such that \(\lambda \preccurlyeq p\) on \(X\). \ac{Schechter} \cite{1996b}

373-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\aleph_0,n,\infty)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
373-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\aleph_0,n,\infty)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

373-n

(For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) \(PC(\aleph_0,n,\infty)\): Every denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets has an infinite subset with a choice function.

374-n

\(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
374-n

\(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable.

374-n

\(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable.

375

Tietze-Urysohn Extension Theorem: If \((X,T)\) is a normal topological space, \(A\) is closed in \(X\), and \(f: A\to [0,1]\) is continuous, then there exists a continuous function \(g: X\to [0,1]\) which extends \(f\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
375

Tietze-Urysohn Extension Theorem: If \((X,T)\) is a normal topological space, \(A\) is closed in \(X\), and \(f: A\to [0,1]\) is continuous, then there exists a continuous function \(g: X\to [0,1]\) which extends \(f\).

375

Tietze-Urysohn Extension Theorem: If \((X,T)\) is a normal topological space, \(A\) is closed in \(X\), and \(f: A\to [0,1]\) is continuous, then there exists a continuous function \(g: X\to [0,1]\) which extends \(f\).

376

Restricted Kinna Wagner Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for every \(z\subseteq Y\), if \(|z| \ge 2\) then \(f(z)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(z\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
376

Restricted Kinna Wagner Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for every \(z\subseteq Y\), if \(|z| \ge 2\) then \(f(z)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(z\).

376

Restricted Kinna Wagner Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for every \(z\subseteq Y\), if \(|z| \ge 2\) then \(f(z)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(z\).

377

Restricted Ordering Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that \(Y\) can be linearly ordered.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
377

Restricted Ordering Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that \(Y\) can be linearly ordered.

377

Restricted Ordering Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that \(Y\) can be linearly ordered.

378

Restricted Choice for Families of Well Ordered Sets:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that the family of non-empty well orderable subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
378

Restricted Choice for Families of Well Ordered Sets:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that the family of non-empty well orderable subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

378

Restricted Choice for Families of Well Ordered Sets:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) such that the family of non-empty well orderable subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function.

379

\(PKW(\infty,\infty,\infty)\): For every infinite family \(X\) of sets each of which has at least two elements, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in Y\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(y\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
379

\(PKW(\infty,\infty,\infty)\): For every infinite family \(X\) of sets each of which has at least two elements, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in Y\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(y\).

379

\(PKW(\infty,\infty,\infty)\): For every infinite family \(X\) of sets each of which has at least two elements, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in Y\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(y\).

380

\(PC(\infty,WO,\infty)\):  For every infinite family of non-empty well orderable sets, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) which has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
380

\(PC(\infty,WO,\infty)\):  For every infinite family of non-empty well orderable sets, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) which has a choice function.

380

\(PC(\infty,WO,\infty)\):  For every infinite family of non-empty well orderable sets, there is an infinite subfamily \(Y\) of \(X\) which has a choice function.

381

DUM:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
381

DUM:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

381

DUM:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

382

DUMN:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is normal.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
382

DUMN:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is normal.

382

DUMN:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is normal.

384

Closed Filter Extendability for \(T_1\) Spaces: Every closed filter in a \(T_1\) topological space can be extended to a maximal closed filter.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
384

Closed Filter Extendability for \(T_1\) Spaces: Every closed filter in a \(T_1\) topological space can be extended to a maximal closed filter.

384

Closed Filter Extendability for \(T_1\) Spaces: Every closed filter in a \(T_1\) topological space can be extended to a maximal closed filter.

385

Countable Ultrafilter Theorem:  Every proper filter with a countable base over a set \(S\) (in \({\cal P}(S)\)) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
385

Countable Ultrafilter Theorem:  Every proper filter with a countable base over a set \(S\) (in \({\cal P}(S)\)) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

385

Countable Ultrafilter Theorem:  Every proper filter with a countable base over a set \(S\) (in \({\cal P}(S)\)) can be extended to an ultrafilter.

386

Every B compact (pseudo)metric space is Baire.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
386

Every B compact (pseudo)metric space is Baire.

386

Every B compact (pseudo)metric space is Baire.

387

DPO:  Every infinite set has a non-trivial, dense partial order.  (A partial ordering \(<\) on a set \(X\) is dense if \((\forall x, y\in X)(x \lt y \to (\exists z \in X)(x \lt z \lt y))\) and is non-trivial if \((\exists x,y\in X)(x \lt y)\)).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
387

DPO:  Every infinite set has a non-trivial, dense partial order.  (A partial ordering \(<\) on a set \(X\) is dense if \((\forall x, y\in X)(x \lt y \to (\exists z \in X)(x \lt z \lt y))\) and is non-trivial if \((\exists x,y\in X)(x \lt y)\)).

387

DPO:  Every infinite set has a non-trivial, dense partial order.  (A partial ordering \(<\) on a set \(X\) is dense if \((\forall x, y\in X)(x \lt y \to (\exists z \in X)(x \lt z \lt y))\) and is non-trivial if \((\exists x,y\in X)(x \lt y)\)).

388

Every infinite branching poset (a partially ordered set in which each element has at least two lower bounds) has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
388

Every infinite branching poset (a partially ordered set in which each element has at least two lower bounds) has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

388

Every infinite branching poset (a partially ordered set in which each element has at least two lower bounds) has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain.

389

\(C(\aleph_0,2,\cal P({\Bbb R}))\): Every denumerable family of two element subsets of \(\cal P({\Bbb R})\) has a choice function.  \ac{Keremedis} \cite{1999b}.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
389

\(C(\aleph_0,2,\cal P({\Bbb R}))\): Every denumerable family of two element subsets of \(\cal P({\Bbb R})\) has a choice function.  \ac{Keremedis} \cite{1999b}.

389

\(C(\aleph_0,2,\cal P({\Bbb R}))\): Every denumerable family of two element subsets of \(\cal P({\Bbb R})\) has a choice function.  \ac{Keremedis} \cite{1999b}.

390

Every infinite set can be partitioned either into two infinite sets or infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

0
 \(0 = 0\).
390

Every infinite set can be partitioned either into two infinite sets or infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

390

Every infinite set can be partitioned either into two infinite sets or infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

391

\(C(\infty,LO)\): Every set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
391

\(C(\infty,LO)\): Every set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

391

\(C(\infty,LO)\): Every set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

392

\(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

393

\(C(LO,WO)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty well orderable sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
393

\(C(LO,WO)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty well orderable sets has a choice function.

393

\(C(LO,WO)\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty well orderable sets has a choice function.

394

\(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
394

\(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

394

\(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function.

395

\(MC(LO,LO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
395

\(MC(LO,LO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

395

\(MC(LO,LO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

396

\(MC(LO,WO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty well orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
396

\(MC(LO,WO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty well orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

396

\(MC(LO,WO)\): For each linearly ordered family of non-empty well orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

397

\(MC(WO,LO)\): For each well ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
397

\(MC(WO,LO)\): For each well ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

397

\(MC(WO,LO)\): For each well ordered family of non-empty linearly orderable sets \(X\), there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in X\) \(f(x)\) is a non-empty, finite subset of \(x\).

398

\(KW(LO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered family of sets: For every linearly ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
398

\(KW(LO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered family of sets: For every linearly ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

398

\(KW(LO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered family of sets: For every linearly ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

399

\(KW(\infty,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a set of linearly orderable sets: For every set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
399

\(KW(\infty,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a set of linearly orderable sets: For every set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

399

\(KW(\infty,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a set of linearly orderable sets: For every set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

400

\(KW(LO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

401

\(KW(LO,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of finite sets: For every linearly ordered set of finite sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
401

\(KW(LO,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of finite sets: For every linearly ordered set of finite sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

401

\(KW(LO,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of finite sets: For every linearly ordered set of finite sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

402

\(KW(WO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every well ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
402

\(KW(WO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every well ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

402

\(KW(WO,LO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered set of linearly orderable sets: For every well ordered set of linearly orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

403

\(KW(LO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of well orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of well orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
403

\(KW(LO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of well orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of well orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

403

\(KW(LO,WO)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a linearly ordered set of well orderable sets: For every linearly ordered set of well orderable sets \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).

404

Every infinite set can be partitioned into infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

0
 \(0 = 0\).
404

Every infinite set can be partitioned into infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

404

Every infinite set can be partitioned into infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983].

405

Every infinite set can be partitioned into sets each of which is countable and has at least two elements.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
405

Every infinite set can be partitioned into sets each of which is countable and has at least two elements.

405

Every infinite set can be partitioned into sets each of which is countable and has at least two elements.

406

The product of compact Hausdorf spaces is countably compact. Alas [1994].

0
 \(0 = 0\).
406

The product of compact Hausdorf spaces is countably compact. Alas [1994].

406

The product of compact Hausdorf spaces is countably compact. Alas [1994].

407

Let \(B\) be a Boolean algebra, \(b\) a non-zero element of \(B\) and \(\{A_i: i\in\omega\}\) a sequence of subsets of \(B\) such that for each \(i\in\omega\), \(A_i\) has a supremum \(a_i\). Then there exists an ultrafilter \(D\) in \(B\) such that \(b\in D\) and, for each \(i\in\omega\), if \(a_i\in D\), then \(D\cap\ A_i\neq\emptyset\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
407

Let \(B\) be a Boolean algebra, \(b\) a non-zero element of \(B\) and \(\{A_i: i\in\omega\}\) a sequence of subsets of \(B\) such that for each \(i\in\omega\), \(A_i\) has a supremum \(a_i\). Then there exists an ultrafilter \(D\) in \(B\) such that \(b\in D\) and, for each \(i\in\omega\), if \(a_i\in D\), then \(D\cap\ A_i\neq\emptyset\).

407

Let \(B\) be a Boolean algebra, \(b\) a non-zero element of \(B\) and \(\{A_i: i\in\omega\}\) a sequence of subsets of \(B\) such that for each \(i\in\omega\), \(A_i\) has a supremum \(a_i\). Then there exists an ultrafilter \(D\) in \(B\) such that \(b\in D\) and, for each \(i\in\omega\), if \(a_i\in D\), then \(D\cap\ A_i\neq\emptyset\).

408

If \(\{f_i: i\in I\}\) is a family of functions such that for each \(i\in I\), \(f_i\subseteq E\times W\), where \(E\) and \(W\) are non-empty sets, and \(\cal B\) is a filter base on \(I\) such that

  1. For all \(B\in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f_i\) is defined on \(F\), and
  2. For all \(B \in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there exist at most finitely many functions on \(F\) which are restrictions of the functions \(f_i\) with \(i\in I\),  
then there is a function \(f\) with domain \(E\) such that for each finite \(F\subseteq E\) and each \(B\in\cal B\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f|F = f_i|F\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
408

If \(\{f_i: i\in I\}\) is a family of functions such that for each \(i\in I\), \(f_i\subseteq E\times W\), where \(E\) and \(W\) are non-empty sets, and \(\cal B\) is a filter base on \(I\) such that

  1. For all \(B\in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f_i\) is defined on \(F\), and
  2. For all \(B \in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there exist at most finitely many functions on \(F\) which are restrictions of the functions \(f_i\) with \(i\in I\),  
then there is a function \(f\) with domain \(E\) such that for each finite \(F\subseteq E\) and each \(B\in\cal B\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f|F = f_i|F\).

408

If \(\{f_i: i\in I\}\) is a family of functions such that for each \(i\in I\), \(f_i\subseteq E\times W\), where \(E\) and \(W\) are non-empty sets, and \(\cal B\) is a filter base on \(I\) such that

  1. For all \(B\in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f_i\) is defined on \(F\), and
  2. For all \(B \in\cal B\) and all finite \(F\subseteq E\) there exist at most finitely many functions on \(F\) which are restrictions of the functions \(f_i\) with \(i\in I\),  
then there is a function \(f\) with domain \(E\) such that for each finite \(F\subseteq E\) and each \(B\in\cal B\) there is an \(i\in I\) such that \(f|F = f_i|F\).

409

Suppose \((G,\Gamma)\) is a locally finite graph (i.e. \(G\) is a non-empty set and \(\Gamma\) is a function from \(G\) to \(\cal P(G)\) such that for each \(x\in G\), \(\Gamma(x)\) and \(\Gamma^{-1}\{x\}\) are finite), \(K\) is a finite set of integers, and \(T\) is a function mapping subsets of \(K\) into subsets of \(K\). If for each finite subgraph \((A,\Gamma_A)\) there is a function \(\psi\) such that for each \(x\in A\), \(\psi(x)\in T(\psi[\Gamma_A(x)])\), then there is a function \(\phi\) such that for all \(x\in G\), \(\phi(x)\in T(\phi[\Gamma(x)])\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
409

Suppose \((G,\Gamma)\) is a locally finite graph (i.e. \(G\) is a non-empty set and \(\Gamma\) is a function from \(G\) to \(\cal P(G)\) such that for each \(x\in G\), \(\Gamma(x)\) and \(\Gamma^{-1}\{x\}\) are finite), \(K\) is a finite set of integers, and \(T\) is a function mapping subsets of \(K\) into subsets of \(K\). If for each finite subgraph \((A,\Gamma_A)\) there is a function \(\psi\) such that for each \(x\in A\), \(\psi(x)\in T(\psi[\Gamma_A(x)])\), then there is a function \(\phi\) such that for all \(x\in G\), \(\phi(x)\in T(\phi[\Gamma(x)])\).

409

Suppose \((G,\Gamma)\) is a locally finite graph (i.e. \(G\) is a non-empty set and \(\Gamma\) is a function from \(G\) to \(\cal P(G)\) such that for each \(x\in G\), \(\Gamma(x)\) and \(\Gamma^{-1}\{x\}\) are finite), \(K\) is a finite set of integers, and \(T\) is a function mapping subsets of \(K\) into subsets of \(K\). If for each finite subgraph \((A,\Gamma_A)\) there is a function \(\psi\) such that for each \(x\in A\), \(\psi(x)\in T(\psi[\Gamma_A(x)])\), then there is a function \(\phi\) such that for all \(x\in G\), \(\phi(x)\in T(\phi[\Gamma(x)])\).

410

RC (Reflexive Compactness): The closed unit ball of a reflexive normed space is compact for the weak topology.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
410

RC (Reflexive Compactness): The closed unit ball of a reflexive normed space is compact for the weak topology.

410

RC (Reflexive Compactness): The closed unit ball of a reflexive normed space is compact for the weak topology.

411

RCuc (Reflexive Compactness for uniformly convex Banach spaces): The closed unit ball of a uniformly convex Banach space is compact for the weak topology.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
411

RCuc (Reflexive Compactness for uniformly convex Banach spaces): The closed unit ball of a uniformly convex Banach space is compact for the weak topology.

411

RCuc (Reflexive Compactness for uniformly convex Banach spaces): The closed unit ball of a uniformly convex Banach space is compact for the weak topology.

412

RCh (Reflexive Compactness for Hilbert spaces): The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact for the weak topology.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
412

RCh (Reflexive Compactness for Hilbert spaces): The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact for the weak topology.

412

RCh (Reflexive Compactness for Hilbert spaces): The closed unit ball of a Hilbert space is compact for the weak topology.

413

Every infinite set \(S\) is the union of a set, well-ordered by inclusion, of subsets which are non-equipollent to \(S\).  

0
 \(0 = 0\).
413

Every infinite set \(S\) is the union of a set, well-ordered by inclusion, of subsets which are non-equipollent to \(S\).  

413

Every infinite set \(S\) is the union of a set, well-ordered by inclusion, of subsets which are non-equipollent to \(S\).  

414

Every \(\cal W\)-frame is a \(\cal D\)-frame.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}

0
 \(0 = 0\).
414

Every \(\cal W\)-frame is a \(\cal D\)-frame.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}

414

Every \(\cal W\)-frame is a \(\cal D\)-frame.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}

415

Every \(\cal W\)-compactly generated complete lattice is algebraic.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
415

Every \(\cal W\)-compactly generated complete lattice is algebraic.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}.

415

Every \(\cal W\)-compactly generated complete lattice is algebraic.  \ac{Ern\'e} \cite{2000}.

416

Every non-compact topological space \(S\) is the union of a set that is well-ordered by inclusion and consists of open proper subsets of \(S\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
416

Every non-compact topological space \(S\) is the union of a set that is well-ordered by inclusion and consists of open proper subsets of \(S\).

416

Every non-compact topological space \(S\) is the union of a set that is well-ordered by inclusion and consists of open proper subsets of \(S\).

417

On every non-trivial Banach space there is a non-trivial linear functional (bounded or unbounded).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
417

On every non-trivial Banach space there is a non-trivial linear functional (bounded or unbounded).

417

On every non-trivial Banach space there is a non-trivial linear functional (bounded or unbounded).

418

DUM(\(\aleph_0\)): The countable disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
418

DUM(\(\aleph_0\)): The countable disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

418

DUM(\(\aleph_0\)): The countable disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

419

UT(\(\aleph_0\),cuf,cuf): The union of a denumerable set of cuf sets is cuf. (A set is cuf if it is a countable union of finite sets.)

0
 \(0 = 0\).
419

UT(\(\aleph_0\),cuf,cuf): The union of a denumerable set of cuf sets is cuf. (A set is cuf if it is a countable union of finite sets.)

419

UT(\(\aleph_0\),cuf,cuf): The union of a denumerable set of cuf sets is cuf. (A set is cuf if it is a countable union of finite sets.)

420

\(UT(\aleph_0\),\(\aleph_0\),cuf): The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is cuf.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
420

\(UT(\aleph_0\),\(\aleph_0\),cuf): The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is cuf.

420

\(UT(\aleph_0\),\(\aleph_0\),cuf): The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is cuf.

421
  \(UT(\aleph_0,WO,WO)\): The union of a denumerable set of well orderable sets can be well ordered.
0
 \(0 = 0\).
421
  \(UT(\aleph_0,WO,WO)\): The union of a denumerable set of well orderable sets can be well ordered.
421
  \(UT(\aleph_0,WO,WO)\): The union of a denumerable set of well orderable sets can be well ordered.
422-n

\(UT(WO,n,WO)\), \(n\in \omega-\{0,1\}\): The union of a well ordered set of \(n\) element sets can be well ordered.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
422-n

\(UT(WO,n,WO)\), \(n\in \omega-\{0,1\}\): The union of a well ordered set of \(n\) element sets can be well ordered.

422-n

\(UT(WO,n,WO)\), \(n\in \omega-\{0,1\}\): The union of a well ordered set of \(n\) element sets can be well ordered.

423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

423

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

424
 Every Lindel\"{o}f metric space is super second countable.  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159. \iput{super second countable}
0
 \(0 = 0\).
424
 Every Lindel\"{o}f metric space is super second countable.  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159. \iput{super second countable}
424
 Every Lindel\"{o}f metric space is super second countable.  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159. \iput{super second countable}
425
 For every first countable topological space \((X, \Cal T)\) there is a family \((\Cal D(x))_{x \in X}\) such that \(\forall x \in X\), \(D(x)\) countable local base at \(x\).  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159.
0
 \(0 = 0\).
425
 For every first countable topological space \((X, \Cal T)\) there is a family \((\Cal D(x))_{x \in X}\) such that \(\forall x \in X\), \(D(x)\) countable local base at \(x\).  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159.
425
 For every first countable topological space \((X, \Cal T)\) there is a family \((\Cal D(x))_{x \in X}\) such that \(\forall x \in X\), \(D(x)\) countable local base at \(x\).  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159.
426

If \((X,\cal T) \) is a first countable topological space and \((\cal B(x))_{x\in X}\) is a family such that for all \(x \in X\), \(\cal B(x)\) is a local base at \(x\), then there is a family \(( \cal V(x))_{x\in X}\) such that for every \(x \in X\), \(\cal V(x)\) is a countable local base at \(x\) and \(\cal V(x) \subseteq \cal B(x)\).

0
 \(0 = 0\).
426

If \((X,\cal T) \) is a first countable topological space and \((\cal B(x))_{x\in X}\) is a family such that for all \(x \in X\), \(\cal B(x)\) is a local base at \(x\), then there is a family \(( \cal V(x))_{x\in X}\) such that for every \(x \in X\), \(\cal V(x)\) is a countable local base at \(x\) and \(\cal V(x) \subseteq \cal B(x)\).

426

If \((X,\cal T) \) is a first countable topological space and \((\cal B(x))_{x\in X}\) is a family such that for all \(x \in X\), \(\cal B(x)\) is a local base at \(x\), then there is a family \(( \cal V(x))_{x\in X}\) such that for every \(x \in X\), \(\cal V(x)\) is a countable local base at \(x\) and \(\cal V(x) \subseteq \cal B(x)\).

427
\(\exists F\) AL20(\(F\)): There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that every independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis.  \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, AL20}.
0
 \(0 = 0\).
427
\(\exists F\) AL20(\(F\)): There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that every independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis.  \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, AL20}.
427
\(\exists F\) AL20(\(F\)): There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space \(V\) over \(F\) has the property that every independent subset of \(V\) can be extended to a basis.  \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, AL20}.
428
\(\exists F\) B\((F)\):  There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space over \(F\) has a basis. \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
0
 \(0 = 0\).
428
\(\exists F\) B\((F)\):  There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space over \(F\) has a basis. \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
428
\(\exists F\) B\((F)\):  There is a field \(F\) such that every vector space over \(F\) has a basis. \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
429-p
(Where \(p\) is a prime) B: Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
0
 \(0 = 0\).
429-p
(Where \(p\) is a prime) B: Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
429-p
(Where \(p\) is a prime) B: Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has a basis.  (\(\mathbb Z_p\) is the \(p\) element field.) \ac{Bleicher} \cite{1964}, \ac{Rubin, H.\/Rubin, J \cite{1985, p.119, B}.
430-p

(Where \(p\) is a prime) \(AL21\)\((p)\): Every vector space over \(\mathbb Z_p\) has the property that for every subspace \(S\) of \(V\), there is a subspace \(S'\) of \(V\) such that \(S \cap S' = \{ 0 \}\) and \(S \cup S'\) generates \(V\) in other words such that \(V = S \oplus S'\).   Rubin, H./Rubin, J [1985], p.119, AL21.

0
 \(0 = 0\).
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

164

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite subset with a Dedekind finite power set.

Brunner-1982a,
164

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite subset with a Dedekind finite power set.

163

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite, Dedekind finite subset.

Brunner-1982a,
88

  \(C(\infty ,2)\):  Every family of pairs has a choice function.

111

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

322

\(KW(WO,\infty)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a well ordered family of sets: For every  well ordered set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\).  (See Form 15).

167

\(PKW(\aleph_{0},\ge 2,\infty)\), Partial Kinna-Wagner Principle:  For every denumerable family \(F\) such that for all \(x\in F\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is an infinite subset \(H\subseteq F\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in H\), \(\emptyset\neq f(x) \subsetneq x\).

44

\(DC(\aleph _{1})\):  Given a relation \(R\) such that for every  subset \(Y\) of a set \(X\) with \(|Y| < \aleph_{1}\) there is an \(x \in  X\)  with \(Y \mathrel R x\), then there is a function \(f: \aleph_{1} \rightarrow  X\) such that \((\forall\beta < \aleph_{1}) (\{f(\gamma ): \gamma < b \} \mathrel R f(\beta))\).

135

If \(X\) is a \(T_2\) space with at least two points and \(X^{Y}\) is hereditarily metacompact then \(Y\) is  countable. (A space is metacompact if every open cover has an open point finite refinement. If \(B\) and \(B'\) are covers of a space \(X\), then \(B'\) is a refinement of \(B\) if \((\forall x\in B')(\exists y\in B)(x\subseteq y)\). \(B\) is point finite if \((\forall t\in X)\) there are only finitely many \(x\in B\) such that \(t\in x\).) van Douwen [1980]

Note 120,
133
 

Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.

163

Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite, Dedekind finite subset.

126

\(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\).

5

\(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function.

132

\(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\):  Every infinite family of finite  sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.

166

\(PC(\infty,2,\infty)\): Every infinite family of pairs has an infinite subfamily with a choice function.