We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:

214 \(\Rightarrow\) 374-n
given by the following sequence of implications, with a reference to its direct proof:

Implication Reference
214 \(\Rightarrow\) 9 clear
9 \(\Rightarrow\) 10 Zermelo's Axiom of Choice, Moore, 1982, 322
10 \(\Rightarrow\) 423 clear
423 \(\Rightarrow\) 374-n clear

Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:

Howard-Rubin Number Statement
214:

\(Z(\omega)\): For every family \(A\) of infinite sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in A\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty subset of \(y\) and \(|f(y)|=\aleph_{0}\).

9:

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

10:

\(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\):  Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

423:

\(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in  \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

374-n:

\(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable.

Comment:

Back