We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
407 \(\Rightarrow\) 14 |
Effective equivalents of the Rasiowa-Sikorski lemma, Bacsich, P. D. 1972b, J. London Math. Soc. Ser. 2. |
14 \(\Rightarrow\) 141 |
Generalizing Konigs infinity lemma, Cowen, R.H. 1977b, Notre Dame J. Formal Logic |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
407: | Let \(B\) be a Boolean algebra, \(b\) a non-zero element of \(B\) and \(\{A_i: i\in\omega\}\) a sequence of subsets of \(B\) such that for each \(i\in\omega\), \(A_i\) has a supremum \(a_i\). Then there exists an ultrafilter \(D\) in \(B\) such that \(b\in D\) and, for each \(i\in\omega\), if \(a_i\in D\), then \(D\cap\ A_i\neq\emptyset\). |
14: | BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal. |
141: | [14 P(\(n\))] with \(n = 2\): Let \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\) be a collection of sets such that \(\forall i\in I,\ |A(i)|\le 2\) and suppose \(R\) is a symmetric binary relation on \(\bigcup^{}_{i\in I} A(i)\) such that for all finite \(W\subseteq I\) there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i \in W\}\). Then there is an \(R\) consistent choice function for \(\{A(i): i\in I\}\). |
Comment: