We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:

15 \(\Rightarrow\) 111
given by the following sequence of implications, with a reference to its direct proof:

Implication Reference
15 \(\Rightarrow\) 30 The Axiom of Choice, Jech, 1973b, page 53 problem 4.12
30 \(\Rightarrow\) 62 clear
62 \(\Rightarrow\) 121 clear
121 \(\Rightarrow\) 122 clear
122 \(\Rightarrow\) 250 clear
250 \(\Rightarrow\) 111 clear

Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:

Howard-Rubin Number Statement
15:

\(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every  set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)).  

30:

Ordering Principle: Every set can be linearly ordered.

62:

\(C(\infty,< \aleph_{0})\):  Every set of non-empty finite  sets  has  a choice function.

121:

\(C(LO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every linearly ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

122:

\(C(WO,<\aleph_{0})\): Every well ordered set of non-empty finite sets has a choice function.

250:

\((\forall n\in\omega-\{0,1\})(C(WO,n))\): For every natural number \(n\ge 2\), every well ordered family of \(n\) element sets has a choice function.

111:

\(UT(WO,2,WO)\): The union of an infinite well ordered set of 2-element sets is an infinite well ordered set.

Comment:

Back