We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
17 \(\Rightarrow\) 132 |
Amorphe Potenzen kompakter Raume, Brunner, N. 1984b, Arch. Math. Logik Grundlagenforschung |
132 \(\Rightarrow\) 10 |
Amorphe Potenzen kompakter Raume, Brunner, N. 1984b, Arch. Math. Logik Grundlagenforschung |
10 \(\Rightarrow\) 423 | clear |
423 \(\Rightarrow\) 374-n | clear |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
17: | Ramsey's Theorem I: If \(A\) is an infinite set and the family of all 2 element subsets of \(A\) is partitioned into 2 sets \(X\) and \(Y\), then there is an infinite subset \(B\subseteq A\) such that all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(X\) or all 2 element subsets of \(B\) belong to \(Y\). (Also, see Form 325.), Jech [1973b], p 164 prob 11.20. |
132: | \(PC(\infty, <\aleph_0,\infty)\): Every infinite family of finite sets has an infinite subfamily with a choice function. |
10: | \(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function. |
423: | \(\forall n\in \omega-\{o,1\}\), \(C(\aleph_0, n)\) : For every \(n\in \omega - \{0,1\}\), every denumerable set of \(n\) element sets has a choice function. |
374-n: | \(UT(\aleph_0,n,\aleph_0)\) for \(n\in\omega -\{0,1\}\): The union of a denumerable set of \(n\)-element sets is denumerable. |
Comment: