We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
303 \(\Rightarrow\) 50 |
Some propositions equivalent to the Sikorski extension theorem for Boolean algebras, Bell, J.L. 1988, Fund. Math. |
50 \(\Rightarrow\) 14 |
A survey of recent results in set theory, Mathias, A.R.D. 1979, Period. Math. Hungar. |
14 \(\Rightarrow\) 270 |
Restricted versions of the compactness theorem, Kolany, A. 1991, Rep. Math. Logic |
270 \(\Rightarrow\) 271-n |
Restricted versions of the compactness theorem, Kolany, A. 1991, Rep. Math. Logic |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
303: | If \(B\) is a Boolean algebra, \(S\subseteq B\) and \(S\) is closed under \(\land\), then there is a \(\subseteq\)-maximal proper ideal \(I\) of \(B\) such that \(I\cap S= \{0\}\). |
50: | Sikorski's Extension Theorem: Every homomorphism of a subalgebra \(B\) of a Boolean algebra \(A\) into a complete Boolean algebra \(B'\) can be extended to a homomorphism of \(A\) into \(B'\). Sikorski [1964], p. 141. |
14: | BPI: Every Boolean algebra has a prime ideal. |
270: | \(CT_{\hbox{fin}}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs only in a finite number of formulas. |
271-n: | If \(n\in\omega-\{0,1\}\), \(CT_{n}\): The compactness theorem for propositional logic restricted to sets of formulas in which each variable occurs in at most \(n\) formulas. |
Comment: