We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:

2 \(\Rightarrow\) 167
given by the following sequence of implications, with a reference to its direct proof:

Implication Reference
2 \(\Rightarrow\) 3 On successors in cardinal arithmetic, Truss, J. K. 1973c, Fund. Math.
3 \(\Rightarrow\) 9 Cardinal addition and the axiom of choice, Howard, P. 1974, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc.
9 \(\Rightarrow\) 376 clear
376 \(\Rightarrow\) 167 clear

Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:

Howard-Rubin Number Statement
2:

Existence of successor cardinals: For every cardinal \(m\) there is a cardinal \(n\) such that \(m < n\) and \((\forall p < n)(p \le m)\).

3:  \(2m = m\): For all infinite cardinals \(m\), \(2m = m\).
9:

Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite.

376:

Restricted Kinna Wagner Principle:  For every infinite set \(X\) there is an infinite subset \(Y\) of \(X\) and a function \(f\) such that for every \(z\subseteq Y\), if \(|z| \ge 2\) then \(f(z)\) is a non-empty proper subset of \(z\).

167:

\(PKW(\aleph_{0},\ge 2,\infty)\), Partial Kinna-Wagner Principle:  For every denumerable family \(F\) such that for all \(x\in F\), \(|x|\ge 2\), there is an infinite subset \(H\subseteq F\) and a function \(f\) such that for all \(x\in H\), \(\emptyset\neq f(x) \subsetneq x\).

Comment:

Back