We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
12 \(\Rightarrow\) 336-n | clear |
336-n \(\Rightarrow\) 64 |
Weak choice principles, De la Cruz, O. 1998a, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. |
64 \(\Rightarrow\) 127 |
Amorphe Potenzen kompakter Raume, Brunner, N. 1984b, Arch. Math. Logik Grundlagenforschung |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
12: | A Form of Restricted Choice for Families of Finite Sets: For every infinite set \(A\) and every \(n\in\omega\), there is an infinite subset \(B\) of \(A\) such the set of all \(n\) element subsets of \(B\) has a choice function. De la Cruz/Di Prisco} [1998b] |
336-n: | (For \(n\in\omega\), \(n\ge 2\).) For every infinite set \(X\), there is an infinite \(Y \subseteq X\) such that the set of all \(n\)-element subsets of \(Y\) has a choice function. |
64: | \(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.) |
127: | An amorphous power of a compact \(T_2\) space, which as a set is well orderable, is well orderable. |
Comment: