We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
164 \(\Rightarrow\) 91 |
Dedekind-Endlichkeit und Wohlordenbarkeit, Brunner, N. 1982a, Monatsh. Math. |
91 \(\Rightarrow\) 79 | clear |
79 \(\Rightarrow\) 94 | clear |
94 \(\Rightarrow\) 5 | clear |
5 \(\Rightarrow\) 38 |
Non-constructive properties of the real numbers, Howard, P. 2001, Math. Logic Quart. |
38 \(\Rightarrow\) 108 | clear |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
164: | Every non-well-orderable set has an infinite subset with a Dedekind finite power set. |
91: | \(PW\): The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered. |
79: | \({\Bbb R}\) can be well ordered. Hilbert [1900], p 263. |
94: | \(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1. |
5: | \(C(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function. |
38: | \({\Bbb R}\) is not the union of a countable family of countable sets. |
108: | There is an ordinal \(\alpha\) such that \(2^{\aleph _{\alpha}}\) is not the union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets. |
Comment: