We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
188 \(\Rightarrow\) 106 |
Injectivity, projectivity and the axiom of choice, Blass, A. 1979, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. |
106 \(\Rightarrow\) 126 |
Injectivity, projectivity and the axiom of choice, Blass, A. 1979, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. |
126 \(\Rightarrow\) 82 | note-76 |
82 \(\Rightarrow\) 83 |
Definitions of finite, Howard, P. 1989, Fund. Math. |
83 \(\Rightarrow\) 64 | The Axiom of Choice, Jech, 1973b, page 52 problem 4.10 |
64 \(\Rightarrow\) 390 | clear |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
188: | \(EP\ Ab\): For every Abelian group \(A\) there is a projective Abelian group \(G\) and a homomorphism from \(G\) onto \(A\). |
106: | Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire. |
126: | \(MC(\aleph_0,\infty)\), Countable axiom of multiple choice: For every denumerable set \(X\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\). |
82: | \(E(I,III)\) (Howard/Yorke [1989]): If \(X\) is infinite then \(\cal P(X)\) is Dedekind infinite. (\(X\) is finite \(\Leftrightarrow {\cal P}(X)\) is Dedekind finite.) |
83: | \(E(I,II)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]: \(T\)-finite is equivalent to finite. |
64: | \(E(I,Ia)\) There are no amorphous sets. (Equivalently, every infinite set is the union of two disjoint infinite sets.) |
390: | Every infinite set can be partitioned either into two infinite sets or infinitely many sets, each of which has at least two elements. Ash [1983]. |
Comment: