We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
391 \(\Rightarrow\) 112 | clear |
112 \(\Rightarrow\) 90 | Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice II, Rubin/Rubin, 1985, page 79 |
90 \(\Rightarrow\) 91 | The Axiom of Choice, Jech, 1973b, page 133 |
91 \(\Rightarrow\) 305 | Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice II, Rubin, 1985, theorem 5.7 |
305 \(\Rightarrow\) 307 | clear |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
391: | \(C(\infty,LO)\): Every set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function. |
112: | \(MC(\infty,LO)\): For every family \(X\) of non-empty sets each of which can be linearly ordered there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(y\in X\), \(f(y)\) is a non-empty finite subset of \(y\). |
90: | \(LW\): Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133. |
91: | \(PW\): The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered. |
305: | There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Vitali equivalence classes. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).). \ac{Kanovei} \cite{1991}. |
307: | If \(m\) is the cardinality of the set of Vitali equivalence classes, then \(H(m) = H(2^{\aleph_0})\), where \(H\) is Hartogs aleph function and the {\it Vitali equivalence classes} are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in {\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\). |
Comment: