We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
394 \(\Rightarrow\) 165 | clear |
165 \(\Rightarrow\) 32 | clear |
32 \(\Rightarrow\) 10 | clear |
10 \(\Rightarrow\) 358 | clear |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
394: | \(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function. |
165: | \(C(WO,WO)\): Every well ordered family of non-empty, well orderable sets has a choice function. |
32: | \(C(\aleph_0,\le\aleph_0)\): Every denumerable set of non-empty countable sets has a choice function. |
10: | \(C(\aleph_{0},< \aleph_{0})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty finite sets has a choice function. |
358: | \(KW(\aleph_0,<\aleph_0)\), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle for a denumerable family of finite sets: For every denumerable set \(M\) of finite sets there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A| > 1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). |
Comment: