We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
264 \(\Rightarrow\) 202 |
Variations of Zorn's lemma, principles of cofinality, and Hausdorff's maximal principle, Part I and II, Harper, J. 1976, Notre Dame J. Formal Logic |
202 \(\Rightarrow\) 40 | clear |
40 \(\Rightarrow\) 86-alpha | clear |
86-alpha \(\Rightarrow\) 196-alpha |
Successive large cardinals, Bull Jr., E. L. 1978, Ann. Math. Logic |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
264: | \(H(C,P)\): Every connected relation \((X,R)\) contains a \(\subseteq\)-maximal partially ordered set. |
202: | \(C(LO,\infty)\): Every linearly ordered family of non-empty sets has a choice function. |
40: | \(C(WO,\infty)\): Every well orderable set of non-empty sets has a choice function. Moore, G. [1982], p 325. |
86-alpha: | \(C(\aleph_{\alpha},\infty)\): If \(X\) is a set of non-empty sets such that \(|X| = \aleph_{\alpha }\), then \(X\) has a choice function. |
196-alpha: | \(\aleph_{\alpha}\) and \(\aleph_{\alpha+1}\) are not both measurable. |
Comment: