We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:

335-n \(\Rightarrow\) 425
given by the following sequence of implications, with a reference to its direct proof:

Implication Reference
335-n \(\Rightarrow\) 333 Bases for vector spaces over the two element field and the axiom of choice, Keremedis, K. 1996a, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc.
333 \(\Rightarrow\) 67 clear
67 \(\Rightarrow\) 76 clear
76 \(\Rightarrow\) 425 On first and second countable spaces and the axiom of choice, Gutierres, G 2004, Topology and its Applications.

Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:

Howard-Rubin Number Statement
335-n:

Every quotient group of an Abelian group each of whose elements has order  \(\le n\) has a set of representatives.

333:

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

67:

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

76:

\(MC_\omega(\infty,\infty)\) (\(\omega\)-MC): For every family \(X\) of pairwise disjoint non-empty sets, there is a function \(f\) such that for each \(x\in X\), f(x) is a non-empty countable subset of \(x\).

425:  For every first countable topological space \((X, \Cal T)\) there is a family \((\Cal D(x))_{x \in X}\) such that \(\forall x \in X\), \(D(x)\) countable local base at \(x\).  \ac{Gutierres} \cite{2004} and note 159.

Comment:

Back