We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:

335-n \(\Rightarrow\) 420
given by the following sequence of implications, with a reference to its direct proof:

Implication Reference
335-n \(\Rightarrow\) 333 Bases for vector spaces over the two element field and the axiom of choice, Keremedis, K. 1996a, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc.
333 \(\Rightarrow\) 67 clear
67 \(\Rightarrow\) 381 Disjoint unions of topological spaces and choice, Howard, P. 1998b, Math. Logic Quart.
381 \(\Rightarrow\) 418 Metric spaces and the axiom of choice, De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A[2002A], Math. Logic Quart.
418 \(\Rightarrow\) 419 Metric spaces and the axiom of choice, De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A[2002A], Math. Logic Quart.
419 \(\Rightarrow\) 420 Metric spaces and the axiom of choice, De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A[2002A], Math. Logic Quart.

Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:

Howard-Rubin Number Statement
335-n:

Every quotient group of an Abelian group each of whose elements has order  \(\le n\) has a set of representatives.

333:

\(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of  sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that  for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd.

67:

\(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite).

381:

DUM:  The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

418:

DUM(\(\aleph_0\)): The countable disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable.

419:

UT(\(\aleph_0\),cuf,cuf): The union of a denumerable set of cuf sets is cuf. (A set is cuf if it is a countable union of finite sets.)

420:

\(UT(\aleph_0\),\(\aleph_0\),cuf): The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is cuf.

Comment:

Back