We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
335-n \(\Rightarrow\) 333 |
Bases for vector spaces over the two element field and the axiom of choice, Keremedis, K. 1996a, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. |
333 \(\Rightarrow\) 67 | clear |
67 \(\Rightarrow\) 381 |
Disjoint unions of topological spaces and choice, Howard, P. 1998b, Math. Logic Quart. |
381 \(\Rightarrow\) 418 |
Metric spaces and the axiom of choice, De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A[2002A], Math. Logic Quart. |
418 \(\Rightarrow\) 419 |
Metric spaces and the axiom of choice, De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A[2002A], Math. Logic Quart. |
419 \(\Rightarrow\) 420 |
Metric spaces and the axiom of choice, De-la-Cruz-Hall-Howard-Keremedis-Rubin-2002A[2002A], Math. Logic Quart. |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
335-n: | Every quotient group of an Abelian group each of whose elements has order \(\le n\) has a set of representatives. |
333: | \(MC(\infty,\infty,\mathrm{odd})\): For every set \(X\) of sets such that for all \(x\in X\), \(|x|\ge 1\), there is a function \(f\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a finite, non-empty subset of \(x\) and \(|f(x)|\) is odd. |
67: | \(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite). |
381: | DUM: The disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable. |
418: | DUM(\(\aleph_0\)): The countable disjoint union of metrizable spaces is metrizable. |
419: | UT(\(\aleph_0\),cuf,cuf): The union of a denumerable set of cuf sets is cuf. (A set is cuf if it is a countable union of finite sets.) |
420: | \(UT(\aleph_0\),\(\aleph_0\),cuf): The union of a denumerable set of denumerable sets is cuf. |
Comment: