We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
392 \(\Rightarrow\) 394 | clear |
394 \(\Rightarrow\) 337 | clear |
337 \(\Rightarrow\) 92 | clear |
92 \(\Rightarrow\) 94 | clear |
94 \(\Rightarrow\) 194 | clear |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
392: | \(C(LO,LO)\): Every linearly ordered set of linearly orderable sets has a choice function. |
394: | \(C(WO,LO)\): Every well ordered set of non-empty linearly orderable sets has a choice function. |
337: | \(C(WO\), uniformly linearly ordered): If \(X\) is a well ordered collection of non-empty sets and there is a function \(f\) defined on \(X\) such that for every \(x\in X\), \(f(x)\) is a linear ordering of \(x\), then there is a choice function for \(X\). |
92: | \(C(WO,{\Bbb R})\): Every well ordered family of non-empty subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) has a choice function. |
94: | \(C(\aleph_{0},\infty,{\Bbb R})\): Every denumerable family of non-empty sets of reals has a choice function. Jech [1973b], p 148 prob 10.1. |
194: | \(C(\varPi^1_2)\) or \(AC(\varPi^1_2)\): If \(P\in \omega\times{}^{\omega}\omega\), \(P\) has domain \(\omega\), and \(P\) is in \(\varPi^1_2\), then there is a sequence of elements \(\langle x_{k}: k\in\omega\rangle\) of \({}^{\omega}\omega\) with \(\langle k,x_{k}\rangle \in P\) for all \(k\in\omega\). Kanovei [1979]. |
Comment: