Fraenkel \(\cal N16\): Jech/Levy/Pincus Model | Back to this models page
Description: \(A\) has cardinality \(\aleph_{\omega}\);\(\cal G\) is the group of all permutations on \(A\); and \(S\) is the set ofall subsets of \(A\) of cardinality less that \(\aleph_{\omega}\)
When the book was first being written, only the following form classes were known to be true in this model:
Form Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
6 | \(UT(\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\aleph_0,\Bbb R)\): The union of a denumerable family of denumerable subsets of \({\Bbb R}\) is denumerable. |
9 | Finite \(\Leftrightarrow\) Dedekind finite: \(W_{\aleph_{0}}\) Jech [1973b]: \(E(I,IV)\) Howard/Yorke [1989]): Every Dedekind finite set is finite. |
37 | Lebesgue measure is countably additive. |
41 | \(W_{\aleph _{1}}\): For every cardinal \(m\), \(m \le \aleph_{1}\) or \(\aleph_{1}\le m \). |
63 |
\(SPI\): Weak ultrafilter principle: Every infinite set has a non-trivial ultrafilter.
|
91 | \(PW\): The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered. |
130 | \({\cal P}(\Bbb R)\) is well orderable. |
191 | \(SVC\): There is a set \(S\) such that for every set \(a\), there is an ordinal \(\alpha\) and a function from \(S\times\alpha\) onto \(a\). |
273 | There is a subset of \({\Bbb R}\) which is not Borel. |
305 | There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Vitali equivalence classes. (Vitali equivalence classes are equivalence classes of the real numbers under the relation \(x\equiv y\leftrightarrow(\exists q\in{\Bbb Q})(x-y=q)\).). \ac{Kanovei} \cite{1991}. |
309 | The Banach-Tarski Paradox: There are three finite partitions \(\{P_1,\ldots\), \(P_n\}\), \(\{Q_1,\ldots,Q_r\}\) and \(\{S_1,\ldots,S_n, T_1,\ldots,T_r\}\) of \(B^3 = \{x\in {\Bbb R}^3 : |x| \le 1\}\) such that \(P_i\) is congruent to \(S_i\) for \(1\le i\le n\) and \(Q_i\) is congruent to \(T_i\) for \(1\le i\le r\). |
313 | \(\Bbb Z\) (the set of integers under addition) is amenable. (\(G\) is {\it amenable} if there is a finitely additive measure \(\mu\) on \(\cal P(G)\) such that \(\mu(G) = 1\) and \(\forall A\subseteq G, \forall g\in G\), \(\mu(gA)=\mu(A)\).) |
361 | In \(\Bbb R\), the union of a denumerable number of analytic sets is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325. |
363 | There are exactly \(2^{\aleph_0}\) Borel sets in \(\Bbb R\). G. Moore [1982], p 325. |
368 | The set of all denumerable subsets of \(\Bbb R\) has power \(2^{\aleph_0}\). |
369 | If \(\Bbb R\) is partitioned into two sets, at least one of them has cardinality \(2^{\aleph_0}\). |
When the book was first being written, only the following form classes were known to be false in this model:
Form Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
8 | \(C(\aleph_{0},\infty)\): |
15 | \(KW(\infty,\infty)\) (KW), The Kinna-Wagner Selection Principle: For every set \(M\) there is a function \(f\) such that for all \(A\in M\), if \(|A|>1\) then \(\emptyset\neq f(A)\subsetneq A\). (See Form 81(\(n\)). |
106 | Baire Category Theorem for Compact Hausdorff Spaces: Every compact Hausdorff space is Baire. |
133 | Every set is either well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset. |
Historical background: In thismodel, every infinite set has a countably infinite subset (9 is true), butnot every set of denumerable sets has a choice function (8 is false).Also, in \(\cal N16\), for every cardinal \(\kappa < \aleph_{\omega}\) everycardinal is comparable to \(\kappa\) (41 is true), but there are cardinalsthat are not comparable to \(\aleph_{\omega}\). Form 41 implies that thereare no amorphous sets (64 is true), but 64 implies that 133 (Every set iseither well orderable or has an infinite amorphous subset.) is false.Since 70 (There is a non-trivial ultrafilter on \(\omega\).) is true inevery FM model and 9 + 70 implies 63 (Every infinite set has a non-trivialultrafilter.), 63 is also true.
Back