We have the following indirect implication of form equivalence classes:
Implication | Reference |
---|---|
149 \(\Rightarrow\) 67 |
The axiom of choice in topology, Brunner, N. 1983d, Notre Dame J. Formal Logic note-26 |
67 \(\Rightarrow\) 89 |
On cardinals and their successors, Jech, T. 1966a, Bull. Acad. Polon. Sci. S'er. Sci. Math. Astronom. Phys. |
89 \(\Rightarrow\) 90 | The Axiom of Choice, Jech, 1973b, page 133 |
90 \(\Rightarrow\) 91 | The Axiom of Choice, Jech, 1973b, page 133 |
91 \(\Rightarrow\) 361 | Equivalents of the Axiom of Choice II, Rubin, 1985, theorem 5.7 |
361 \(\Rightarrow\) 362 | Zermelo's Axiom of Choice, Moore, 1982, page 325 |
Here are the links and statements of the form equivalence classes referenced above:
Howard-Rubin Number | Statement |
---|---|
149: | \(A(F)\): Every \(T_2\) topological space is a continuous, finite to one image of an \(A1\) space. |
67: | \(MC(\infty,\infty)\) \((MC)\), The Axiom of Multiple Choice: For every set \(M\) of non-empty sets there is a function \(f\) such that \((\forall x\in M)(\emptyset\neq f(x)\subseteq x\) and \(f(x)\) is finite). |
89: | Antichain Principle: Every partially ordered set has a maximal antichain. Jech [1973b], p 133. |
90: | \(LW\): Every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Jech [1973b], p 133. |
91: | \(PW\): The power set of a well ordered set can be well ordered. |
361: | In \(\Bbb R\), the union of a denumerable number of analytic sets is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325. |
362: | In \(\Bbb R\), every Borel set is analytic. G. Moore [1982], pp 181 and 325. |
Comment: